Magazine: The Monist, April, 1991


   Record: 1
   97052846330026966219910401
   
   Title: Foucault and the spaces of history.
   Subject(s): FOUCAULT, Michel -- Criticism & interpretation; CRITICISM
   Source: Monist, Apr91, Vol. 74 Issue 2, p165, 22p
   Author(s): Flynn, Thomas R.
   Abstract: Discusses the shift of historian Michael Foucault from time
   to space as the paradigm guiding his approach to historical topics.
   Information on Foucault; Reference to other historians; Details on
   some of Foucault's beliefs.
   AN: 9705284633
   ISSN: 0026-9662
   Full Text Word Count: 9209
   Database: Academic Search Elite
   
                     FOUCAULT AND THE SPACES OF HISTORY
                                      
   A critique could be carried out of this devaluation of space [in our
   century]. Did it begin with Bergson, or before? Space was treated as
   the dead, the fixed, the undialectical, the immobile. Time, on the
   contrary, was richness, fecundity, life, dialectic.
   
   What the intellectual can do is provide instruments of analysis, and
   at present this is the historian's essential role. What's effectively
   needed is a ramified, penetrative perception of the present, one that
   makes it possible to locate lines of weakness, strong points,
   positions where the instances of power have secured and implanted
   themselves by a system of organization dating back over 150 years. In
   other words, a topological and geographical survey of the
   battlefield--that is the intellectual's role. (PK 62)
   
   Michel Foucault was a kaleidoscopic thinker.[2] He gathered the
   received opinions, established norms and major facts of our cultural
   heritage and shifted the ensemble ever so slightly. The results were
   startingly new configurations. What had been perceived as necessary
   relationships, inviolable limits, pivotal events, emerged in this
   altered perspective as contingencies that supported quite different
   descriptions. This might simply be subsumed by some narrativist theory
   as evidence that a variety of stories can incorporate the same facts.
   But Foucault shifts the perspective on narrative as well. The chain of
   influences, the temporal continuities, the sustaining consciousness,
   the totalizing dialectic--these dissolve or are relativized by the
   method he employs. In sum, Foucault is an historian, but suo modo.
   Unlike that of the old or even the "new" French historians, his is a
   self-declared history of the present, an objective, he argues, fully
   in accord with the spirit, if not the letter, of the Enlightenment.[3]
   I shall try to illuminate the nature and implications of that original
   approach to history by focusing on one of his most striking
   kaleidoscopic moves, the shift from time to space as the paradigm
   guiding his approach to historical topics (the word topos having a
   primarily spatial denotation). Of course, the kaleidoscope itself is a
   spatial, and indeed an atemporal instrument.
   
                                     I
                                      
   Paul Ricoeur has long done battle with the rising tide of the "New
   History" in French thought.[4] His basic argument has been that such
   history cannot bear the name if it diminishes, much less excludes, the
   temporal character of human experience as integral to the subject it
   studies; time (not just chronological sequence) is ingredient in the
   world of action, and it is this world that history seeks to articulate
   (TN 1:91ff.). Ricoeur's strictures against quantitative and serial
   history arise from his own commitment to hermeneutical phenomenology,
   with its reliance on the ineluctably temporal character of the
   lifeworld (Lebenswelt) as the pretheoretical basis for any
   "scientific" investigation.
   
   The most extreme of theoreticians for the New History, as Ricoeur sees
   it, is Foucault's friend and colleague at the College de France, Paul
   Veyne. With his typical flair for shocking our common sense, Veyne
   asserts: "Time is not essential to history, any more than is the
   individualizing of events that it undergoes in spite of itself .... It
   may seem paradoxical to deny time in history, but it is no less true
   that the concept of time is not indispensable to the historian who has
   need only of that of the intelligible process (we would say, of the
   concept of plot)." (WH 65-66). His larger thesis is that what he calls
   "complete history" must incorporate the "non-eventworthy description
   of contemporary civilization" which has heretofore been left to
   sociology. Indeed, "if history decides to be 'complete'," he goes on
   to say, ". . . it makes sociology useless" (WH 264).$
   
   In Veyne's opinion, two conventions have mutilated history, limiting
   it to a kind of "biography of a national individuality," namely, the
   belief that "there was no history, save for the past" and the
   conviction that "history related the past life of a nation, was
   centered on the special individuality of the latter, and established
   itself in a spatiotemporal continuum" (WH 282-83). Echoing the words
   of Foucault, as we shall see, he recommends, on the contrary, that
   historians emulate the comparativist spirit of general geographers,
   who "never consider a phenomenon without comparing it with related
   phenomena that are spread over the other points of the globe" (WH
   284).
   
   Foucault, who praised Veyne's book for having "rekindled reflection on
   historical methods and concepts in France,"6 has practiced what Veyne
   was preaching, perhaps even subscribing to the latter's "narrativist"
   conviction that the plot (l'intrigue) is essential to history.[7] He
   joins Veyne in violating established history's two conventions with
   his "history of the present," as he styles his book-length works,[8]
   and his concentration on relationships that transcend national
   boundaries as do the scientific community, the bourgeois culture and
   the sociopolitical structures he describes. Particularly during his
   "archaeological" period, when he treated the contrasting
   understandings of insanity (Madness and Civilization), medical
   diagnostic procedure (The Birth of the Clinic), and explanation in the
   social sciences (The Order of Things) before and after the "break"
   associated with the French Revolution and its immediate aftermath,
   Foucault's method was avowedly "differential" somewhat along lines
   recommended by Ferdinand de Saussure in his Course in General
   Linguistics.[9] Moreover, he explicitly credits Georges Dumezil for
   having "taught me to analyze the internal economy of discourse quite
   differently from the traditional methods of exegesis or those of
   linguistic formalism. It is he," Foucault continues in his Inaugural
   Lecture at the College de France, "who taught me to refer the system
   of functional correlations from one discourse to another by means of
   comparison. It was he, again, who taught me to describe the
   transformations of a discourse and its relations to the
   institution."[10] These were the works that earned him the label
   "structuralist," a title he emphatically rejected.
   
   Saussure, we may recall, was able to cordon off a separate and
   autonomous realm called "language" (la langue) as distinct from
   specific speech acts (la parole) in order to articulate the rules of
   formation and transformation of the former in a scientific manner. By
   a kind of methodological suspension of concern for the individual
   practices of speaking, he was freed to seek the "meaning" of signs in
   their relationship of similarity to and difference from other
   linguistic signs. In a famous remark, Saussure asserts: "[In] language
   there are only differences without positive terms. Whether we take the
   signified or the signifier, language has neither ideas nor sounds that
   existed before the linguistic system, but only conceptual and phonic
   differences that have issued from the system."[11] The popular
   understanding of language as basically nomenclautre is systematically
   rejected.
   
   It is the non-subject-centered and relational nature of the
   differential method that appeals to Foucault. He shares Saussure's
   anti-substantialist view of the subject as well as his interest in
   meaning as system-relative, but he rejects the structures of the
   structuralists as axiomatic and formal. Foucault's "structures,"
   whether they be called "epistemes" or "diagrams" (DP 205), are, he
   insists, not at all "transcendental" in the Kantian sense; neither are
   they origins or foundations. They possess a factual character that
   appeals to his "positivist" tendencies; they are to be discovered, not
   deduced.
   
   When he characterizes his method as "diagnostic," he means that it
   yields "a form of knowledge that defines and determines
   differences."[12] The example he cites is a physician determining a
   disease by comparing the symptoms with those of other diseases. He
   seems to have adopted as a general rule what he characterized in The
   Birth of the Clinic as "the diacritical principle of medical
   observation," namely, that "the only pathological fact is a
   comparative fact" (BC 134). This, of course, would accord with his
   kaleidoscopic (what we shall soon call "spatializing") thought.
   
   Foucault's diagnostic method is that of an historical nominalist.[13]
   His entire project has been radically anti-Platonic and favorable to
   those like the Sophists and Cynics in classical antiquity who have
   been marginalized by the official history of Western philosophy. Thus
   his interest in contrast and difference does not imply commitment to
   an underlying unity. True to his nominalist proclivities, he urges:
   
   The freeing of difference requires thought without contradiction,
   without dialectics, without negation; thought that accepts divergence;
   affirmative thought whose instrument is disjunction; thought of the
   multiple--of the nomadic and dispersed multiplicity that is not
   limited or confined by the constraints of similarity .... What is the
   answer to the question? The problem. How is the problem resolved? By
   displacing the question .... We must think problematically rather than
   question and answer dialectically.[14]
   
   This emphasis on "problemization"--on how it came about that sexual
   thoughts as well as practices, for example, became a major moral
   matter, displacing considerations of diet and even civic duty in order
   or importance--though most explicit in his second and third volumes of
   the history of sexuality, was already present in his earlier writings,
   a fact worth noting when addressing the unity of Foucault's thought.
   Problemization, as we shall see, expresses the spatialization of
   language in Foucault's later thought.
   
   Because of his comparatist method, Foucault should be seen as less a
   revisionist than a counter-historian. Each of the "histories" he
   constructs, whether archaeological, genealogical or "problemizing"
   (the last two volumes of his History of Sexuality, for example), are
   dependent on prior histories against which they define themselves in
   differential manner. As the signs in Saussure's system of language
   derive their meaning through a relationship of contrast with other
   signs, so the statements in Foucault's histories gain their
   significance, not only from mutual differences but from the ongoing
   distinction drawn between the set of statements being described and a
   contrasting set in question. It is not simply that the set of
   statements constituting the modern discourse of sexuality, for
   example, displays a coherence that makes some statements possible and
   excludes others or even that the discourse of sexuality creates a
   space in which such statements may proliferate; rather, it is that the
   entire "discursive formation" (the set itself and the rules that
   govern it) assumes its meaning as a mechanism of social control in
   contrast with alternative discourses that allow sex a less decisive,
   cognitive role in constituting social subjects. Accordingly, the
   alternative "bodies and pleasures" that Foucault speaks of at the
   close of his first volume on sexuality have the force of resistance to
   presently dominant discursive practices by virtue of their very
   possibility.[15] Things can be otherwise, he is saying, not merely in
   the utopian sense of imaginative constructions, but in the diagnostic
   contrast that "heterotopias" establish.
   
   In a lecture entitled "Of Other Spaces," delivered the year after The
   Order of Things was published, Foucault undertakes a brief "history"
   of space in support of the thesis that whereas history was the great
   obsession of nineteenth-century thought, our present age could well be
   termed "the epoch of space." He employs his diagnostic method to
   distinguish "Heterotopias" (other places)from "utopias" ("good
   places/no places"). The former, which is a constant of every human
   group, includes such spaces as cemeteries, gardens and museums, as
   well as the "space" of fairs and vacation villages, of libraries and
   colonies. What makes this curious essay interesting, in addition to
   the characteristic insightfulness of Foucault's descriptions, is its
   use of the method of contrast to underscore the "space of
   contemptation" that heterotopias inevitably introduce into a society.
   Although they have a specific function proper to each society within
   which they exist, in general these "other spaces" silently question
   the space in which we live. Again, the diagnostic method illuminates
   the fact that "we live inside an ensemble of relations which define
   sites [emplacements] that are irreducible to and absolutely non
   superposable upon each other."[16] Diagnosis concerning the nature of
   the present, "by following lines of fragility in the present--in
   managing to grasp why and how that-which-is might no longer be
   that-which-is," inevitably opens up what Foucault calls "a space of
   concrete freedom, i.e., of possible transformation."[17]
   
   It is this revelation of the radical contingency of discourses that
   makes Foucault's "histories" forms of social critique, a fact
   seemingly lost on such critics as Habermas and Rorty. And it is
   "space" or rather the spatialization of language, I wish to argue,
   that fills the organizing role in postmodern thought played by "order"
   and "history" in the Classical and Modern epistemic grids
   respectively. To the extent that this reading is correct, one can
   consider Foucault's archaeologies, but also his genealogies and his
   problemizations, as illustrating the very postmodern thought from
   which his "histories" of modernism emerge. In other words, far from
   being a merely stylistic quirk, the discourse of these studies
   exemplifies the postmodern "spatialization" of history in its analysis
   of modern and premodern practices.
   
   In an essay on Maurice Blanchot, whose thought he regarded highly,
   Foucault speaks of "experience of the outside" (l'experience du
   dehors), which historically was lodged in negative theology and in the
   writings of thinkers such as Sade and Holderlin, as reappearing "at
   the very heart of the language" of our culture with the works of
   Nietzsche, Mallarme, Artaud, Bataille, Klossovski and Blanchot
   (members of Foucault's pleiad). Such experience seeks a language that
   excludes the subject, eschews dialectical attempts to recoup
   otherness, and shows an affinity for space, "which is to fiction what
   the negative is to reflection (while dialectical negation is tied to
   the fable of time)."[18] Characterizing with approval Blanchot's
   literary work, Foucault insists that language is "neither truth nor
   time nor eternity nor man, but the ever defeated form of the
   outside."[19] It is in "spatialized" language that Foucault seeks
   liberation, not only from the suzerainty of time and phenomenology,
   whether pure or hermeneutical, but from the metaphor of depth: his is
   a geography, not a geology, or better, a geopolitics of the regions he
   surveys.
   
   In discussing the contrast between clinical and anatomo-clinical
   medicine that surfaced in the early 1800s, for example, Foucault
   notes:
   
   What is modified in giving place to anatomo-clinical medicine is not,
   therefore, the mere surface contact between the knowing subject and
   the known object; it is the more general arrangement of knowledge that
   determines the reciprocal positions and the connections between the
   one who must know and that which is to be known .... It was the result
   of a recasting at the level of epistemic knowledge (savoir) itself,
   and not at the level of accumulated, refined, deepened and adjusted
   knowledge (connaissances) .... It is not a matter of the same game,
   somewhat improved, but of a quite different game. (BC 137)
   
   What he is pointing out is a profound change in the way of looking at
   the patient and a corresponding alteration in the body observed. The
   initial medical query, "What is wrong with you?" leading to a
   classificatory response, gives way to "Where does it hurt?" "The
   notion of seat has finally replaced that of class" (BC 140). This
   basic shift in the twin gears of seeing and saying is indicative, not
   only of an epistemic revolution in nineteenth-century medicine, but of
   the "postmodern" nature of Foucault's own thought. When he prefaces
   his study of clinical medicine with the injunction, "We must place
   ourselves, and remain once and for all, at the level of the
   fundamental spatialization and verbalization of the pathological" (BC
   xi), he is characterizing his general approach to history as well.
   
   Foucault focuses upon what he calls "practice," both discursive and
   nondiscursive,[20] He defines "discourse" as "the group of statements
   that belong to a single system of formation" and what he calls
   "discursive formation," as the regularity that obtains between
   "objects, types of statement, concepts, or thematic choices" (AK 107
   and 38). He insists that the task that The Order of Things set itself
   is one of no longer "treating discourses as groups of signs
   (signifying elements referring to contents or representations) but as
   practices that systematically form the objects of which they speak"
   (AK 49). But he is quick to insist that "the discursive formation is
   characterized not by principles of construction but by a dispersion of
   fact, since for statements it is not a condition of possibility but a
   law of coexistence" (AK 116).
   
   He has admitted that his use of "discourse" in the Archaeology is
   rather ambiguous (see AK 107). The same might be said for" discursive
   formation" which is a condition of existence but not a condition of
   possibility (AK 117), except that here he seems to have adopted this
   distinction to keep his project "positive" and not "transcendental"
   (see AK 230). Indeed, this distinction between conditions of existence
   and of possibility expresses his "principle of exteriority" enunciated
   in the Inaugural Lecture, namely, that rather than burrowing to the
   supposed hidden core of discourse, as hermeneutics, for example, might
   counsel, but instead, "taking the discourse itself, its appearance and
   its regularity, we should look for its external conditions of
   existence, for that which gives rise to chance series of these events
   and fixes its limits" (AK 229). His aim is not to constitute a realm
   independent of the nondiscursive, but to reveal how these formations
   function at the limit between discursive and nondiscursive
   practices--not as representing some extralinguistic reality, but as
   establishing a realm of signs and a specific object of
   investigation.[21]
   
   As if to offer a gloss on Sanssure, Foucault summarizes his method in
   The Archaeology of Knowledge:
   
   What, in short, we wish to do is to dispense with `things.' To
   `depresentify' them .... To substitute for the enigmatic treasure of
   `things' anterior to discourse, the regular formation of objects that
   emerge only in discourse. To define these objects without reference to
   the ground, the foundation of things, but by relating them to the body
   of rules that enable them to form as objects of discourse and thus
   constitute the conditions of their historical appearance. (AK 47-48)
   
   The point of Foucault's analyses in each of these works is to reveal
   the contextualization and radical contingency of our most prized
   certainties. By examining what Veyne calls the "optics of the
   sources," the commonplaces and taken-for-granted's of a particular
   discourse, instituion or set of practices, Foucault is able to reveal
   unsuspected affiliations that challenge the adequacy of our standard
   readings of the phenomena in question and, more importantly,
   constitute new phenomena of their own. As he says with ironic modesty
   of his history of sexuality, "I would like to refocus the perspective
   somewhat: seizing in any case the entire complex of operative
   mechanisms."[22]
   
                                     II
                                      
   But it is not only his comparatist, differential method that I wish to
   pursue, though this is integral to the counter-history he is
   practicing. Foucault's marked preference for spatial metaphors is
   indicative of his synchronic manner of conceiving the relations he
   analyzes. Indeed, rather than refer to precedents and influences such
   as a more temporally ordered discourse might employ, his makes liberal
   use of such terms as displacement, field, position, site, domain and
   limit to convey his grasp of the altered relations his kaleidoscope
   reveals. His writings show a marked prefernce for lists, tables,
   geometrical configurations, and illustrations, that not only
   constitute his particular style of exposition but are integral to the
   argument itself.
   
   Next to the "Panopticon" paradigm of Discipline and Punish, The Order
   of Things offers us the most striking examples of such "spatial"
   arguments. First, there is the example of Velasquez's "Las Meninas"
   which begins the work. In the manner of an art critic, Foucault leads
   us along the path of argument by repeatedly calling our attention to
   aspects of the singular image before us. We are drawn thereby to the
   graphic conclusion that representation cannot represent itself, that
   "the very being of that which is represented is now going to fall
   outside representation itself" (OT 240). The work of Adam Smith in
   economics, of the first philologists, of Jussieu and of Lamarck in
   biology reveal that a "minuscule displacement" has occurred in the
   space of representation, "which toppled the whole of Western thought:
   representation has lost the power to provide a foundation ... for the
   links that can join its various elements together" (OT 238-39). The
   "space of order, which served as a common place for representation and
   for things" in the Classical period is shattered. Henceforth there
   will be things and their representations, but their mutual adequacy
   will have to be established and the "fit" will not be perfect. On the
   threshold of modernity, critical philosophy and positivism will seek
   to occupy that space created by the displacement of being with regard
   to its representations.
   
   Whether he is describing the "anthropological quadrilateral" in
   nineteenth-century thought (namely, finitude, the Kantian
   empirical/transcendental doublet, the unthought underlying the Cogito,
   and historicity) that defines the mode of being of "man" on which the
   social sciences are founded, the epistemological trihedron (formed by
   the deductive sciences, the empirical sciences and philosophical
   reflection) generating the space of the social sciences in the modern
   period, or the open-ended classical "quadrilateral of language"
   centering on the naming relation between thing and its representation,
   Foucault's arguments rely upon these configurations in more than a
   metaphorical sense (see OT 201). They place the human sciences, for
   example, within the boundaries set by mathematics and physical science
   on one side, empirical science on the second side and philosophy on
   the third. This iconic mode of argument brings to our attention not
   only the "essential instability" of the human sciences but their
   inherent danger to the "pure" disciplines that form their boundaries.
   Thus, "psychologism," "sociologism," and what Foucault generically
   terms "anthropologization" constitute a constant danger to the natural
   sciences and philosohy from the human sciences (see OT 348). Like
   Kant's geometrical arguments that relied on the figures for their
   formulation and not merely for their illustration, Foucault's
   quadrilaterials, trihedrons and the like "explain" the limits and
   possibilities created by the relevant epistemes as well as the
   permanent danger, in the case of the trihedron, for example, of
   "anthropologizing" these three planes of knowledge.
   
   Though he is careful to distance himself from deductivist or formalist
   approaches, his archaeological method brings to our attention the
   necessities that these relationships produce. The relations axe a
   priori, albeit "historical" or regional a prioris. Once the
   archaeologist has established the discursive practices, formations and
   rules of formation from the empirical evidence, he/she attempts to
   answer the question "How is it that one particular statement appeared
   rather than another."[9] (AK 27) and why contrasting practices and
   formations are excluded.
   
   Setting his archaeological account against the "tangled network of
   influenoes" that constitutes the standard history of ideas, Foucault
   remarks:
   
   But if we question Classical thought at the level of what,
   archaeologically, made it possible, we perceive that the dissociation
   of the sign and resemblance in the early seventeenth century caused
   these new forms--probability, analysis, combination and universal
   language system--to emerge, not as successive themes engendering one
   another or driving one another out, but as a single network of
   necessities. And it was this network that made possible the
   individuals we term Hobbes, Berkeley, Hume, or Condillac. (OT 63,
   italics mine)
   
   Why one network succeeded another is a matter of chance, a throw of
   the historical dice. But why one appeared with the form it possessed,
   is a function of the "spaces" left vacant by its predecessor. The
   "quasi transcendentals" of life, labor and language, for example,
   filled the gap in the representational schema of the Classical period
   (see OT 206-09), just as the latter displaced the resemblance scheme
   of the Renaissance at the point of its greatest inadequacy. Likewise,
   the famous eighteenth-century debates between mercantilists and
   physiocrats in economics or between practitioners of the Method versus
   the System (evolutionists versus 'fixists') in biology, are just
   "surface disturbances" when viewed archaeologically in comparison, for
   instance, with "the network of necessity which at this point rendered
   the choice between two ways of constituting natural history as a
   language both possible and indispensable. The rest is merely a logical
   and inevitable consequence" (OT 139-40).
   
   But if there is post factum necessity and intelligibility in these
   archaeologies, they float on radial contingency, on the "fundamental
   event" that introduces chance into historical accounts. "The forces at
   play in history," Foucault observes, "obey neither goal nor regulative
   mechanism, but follow the luck of the battle. They do not manifest the
   successive forms of a primordial intention nor do they assume the
   guise of an effect, for they always appear through the singular
   randomness of events."[23]
   
                                    III
                                      
   Reference to "battle" lifts us to the next level in the spiral of
   Foucault's methodological progression, that of genealogy. In its
   opposition to any concept of historical "origins," its emphasis on the
   pivotal role of chance occurrences to "maintain passing events in
   their proper dispersion" (LCP 146), and its Nietzschean nominalism,
   genealogy resembles archaeology. But its apparent difference lies in
   the fact that genealogy "poses the problem of power and of the body
   (of bodies), indeed, its problems begin from the imposition of power
   upon bodies."[24] In retrospect, Foucault insists that he was always
   dealing with the issue of power, and a glance at The Birth of the
   Clinic, above all, would support the claim. But the later method
   complements the earlier one by interpreting all social relations in
   terms of the interplay of forces of domination, resistance and
   control. Not meaning-giving but "warfare" becomes the proper model for
   historical intelligibility, and the basic relation is one of strategy
   and tactics.
   
   Foucault brings to the fore the complementary nature of the
   archaeology/genealogy relation when, shortly after publishing
   Discipline and Punish, he in effect redefines the task of archaeology
   in "genealogical" terms:
   
   The archaeology of the human sciences has to be established through
   studying the mechanisms of power which have invested human bodies,
   acts and forms of behavior. And this investigation enables us to
   rediscover one of the conditions of the emergence of the human
   sciences: the great nineteenth-century effort in discipline and
   normalization. (PK 61)
   
   It was this condition that The Order of Things, subtitled "An
   Archaeology of the Human Sciences," overlooked. His next two
   genealogical studies supplied it.
   
   Now it would seem that a casualty of the move from archaeologyis the
   concept of space itself. One critic, for example, has simply asserted
   that "in his writings of the 1970s Foucault abandons the notion of
   "space"--even the entirely superficial space of an `order of
   discourse.'"[25] What in fact does genealogy have to do with the
   spatialization of history? Does it not rather signal a return to
   genetic and hence to "temporal" issues? In an interview given a
   publication for geographers, Foucault responds:
   
   People have often reproached me for these spatial obsessions, which
   have indeed been obsessions for me. But I think it was through them
   that I came to what I had basically been looking for: the relations
   that are possible between power and knowledge. Once knowledge can be
   analyzed in terms of region, domain, implantation, displacement,
   transposition, one is able to capture the process by which knowledge
   functions as a form of power and disseminates the effects of power.
   There is an administration of knowledge, a politics of knowledge,
   relations of power which pass via knowledge and which, if one tries to
   transcribe them, lead one to consider forms of domination designated
   by such notions as field, region and territory. And the
   politico-strategic term is an indication of how the military and the
   administration actually come to inscribe themselves both on a material
   soil and within forms of discourse (PK 69, translation modified).
   
   It is, in fact, this very spatialized discourse that enables Foucault
   to bring into relation the power/knowledge dyad that comes to
   characterize his genealogical works, especially Discipline and Punish
   and the first volume of The History of Sexuality. "Displacement," for
   example, is a military term and "field" and "region" are
   economico-juridical and administrative notions respectively. We can
   now say that his earlier vocabulary carried an implicit reference to
   relations of domination and control in addition to their being common
   terms for cognition. Indeed, Foucault believes that "anyone envisaging
   the analysis of discourse solely in terms of temporal continuity would
   inevitably be led to approach and analyze it like the internal
   transformation of an individual consciousness. Which would lead to his
   erecting a great collective consciousness as the scene of events." So
   the use of spatial metaphors avoids the "anthropological" bias of
   modern philosophies of history while enabling one "to grasp precisely
   the points at which discourses are transformed in, through and on the
   basis of relations of power" (PK 69-70).
   
   Genealogy underscores the fact that Foucault's is a history of
   "bodies"; not just the body politic, nor the body of information
   (positivity) which a science incarnates, but the physical bodies of
   individuals, tamed, trained, subjected to the scrutinies of experts
   and normalizers. It is a history of physical bodies and the spaces
   they occupy, not "mentalities" or ideologies: controlled and
   anarchical "bodies" as well as the "spaces" that enable them to appear
   as such, not inert matter or abstract, geometrical space; a
   "geography" to be mapped, not a geology to be excavated and
   categorized. Indeed, he shares with Deleuze the belief that
   "difference can only be liberated through the invention of an
   acategorical thought" and that such thinking alone will free us from
   "the neurosis of dialectics" (LCP 186, 184).
   
   Foucault is aware that his valuation of space has been read as
   antihistorical, but he attributes such criticism to "those who confuse
   history with the old schemas of evolution, living continuity, organic
   development, the progress of consciousness or the project of
   existence." What they failed to realize was that "to trace the forms
   of implantation, delimitation and demarcation of objects, the modes of
   tabulation, the organization of domains meant the throwing into relief
   of processes--historical ones, needless to say--of power. The
   spatializing of descriptions of discursive realities," he insists,
   "opens on to the analysis of related effects of power" (PK 70-71,
   translation modified).
   
   Foucault's best known example of spatialized argumentation that
   relates power and knowledge in a more than metaphorical sense is his
   use of Jeremy Bentham's Panopticon to characterize the self-custodial
   nature of our modern, "carceral society," where "prisons resemble
   factories, schools, barracks, hospitals, which all resemble prisons"
   (DP 228). The marriage of norm and surveillance that this interplay of
   architecture and social science exhibits is brilliantly revealed in
   Foucault's descriptions. Again, the demonstrative force of his
   analyses depends upon the spatial organization of the institutions he
   discusses. As with the Velasquez painting, one is constantly referred
   back to the visual evidence, to the plans, the prospects, the models.
   But now the line of sight is strategic, not just descriptive; the
   contours inscribe relations of control, not just forms of
   intelligibility. We are invited to view these practices, institutions
   and sciences as techniques for mastering self and others. This theme
   of self mastery as self constitution will move us up to the final
   level of Foucault's methodological spiral, that of problernization.
   
                                     IV
                                      
   "A few years ago," Foucault observes, "historians were very proud to
   have discovered that they could write not only the history of battles,
   of kings and institutions, but also of the economy. Now they're all
   dumbfounded because the shrewdest among them learned that it was also
   possible to write the history of feelings, of behaviors and of bodies.
   Soon they'll understand that the history of the West cannot be
   disassociated from the way in which "truth" is produced and inscribes
   its effects" (FL 139). At the time of his death, Foucault was said to
   be working on a projected sixvolume study of the history of the
   "production of truth" to have been published in a series under the
   direction of Paul Veyne. His lectures at the College de France that
   year and the previous one on truth-telling (plain speaking, parresia)
   were part of the project.[26]
   
   He defines this new approach to history, "problemization," as "the
   ensemble of discursive and non-discursive practices that makes
   something enter into the play of the true and the false and
   constitutes it an object of thought (whether in the form of moral
   reflection, scientific knowledge, political analysis or the
   like)."[27] Characteristically, he says it is what links all of his
   writings since Madness and Civilization. In that work, for example, it
   was a question of determining how and why at a particular moment
   madness "was problemized via a certain institutional practice and a
   certain cognitive apparatus." Likewise, Discipline and Punish dealt
   with changes in the problemization of relations between penal
   practices and institutions at the end of the seventeenth century. The
   question of his last two books is "how is sexual activity
   problemized?" (SV 18). As I have noted elsewhere, at each spiral of
   his research, Foucault has read the previous turn as in fact dealing
   with what the next professed to study.[28] The relation between truth,
   self-constitution and problemization is worked out in Foucault's later
   writings, enabling him to avow in a volume published just before his
   death that his abiding interest was a "history of truth."[29]
   
   It is noteworthy that Foucault, the apostle of discontinuity, has
   retrospectively sought a coherence throughout his published works. Not
   that he glories in the traditional intellectual values of consistency
   and completeness; on the contrary, he loves to surprise us and himself
   as he follows what he describes as the ethos of the intellectual: to
   think otherwise than before (se deprendre de soi-meme).[30] But there
   has been an identifiable line of advance running through his major
   writings, I have been arguing, that charts the spatialization of
   discourse characteristic of Foucault as a socalled "postmodem"
   thinker. If that claim required some defense in the case of his
   genealogical studies, it would seem most vulnerable with regard to his
   "problemizations."
   
   It is in the contrast Foucault paints between dialectical and
   "problematical" thinking that the spatialization of discourse becomes
   evident. Dialectical thought, he argues, is essentially temporalizing
   thought, to borrow a phrase from Sartre. It seeks a unity and a
   totality in consciousness, whether individual or collective, which is
   itself diachronic. In discussion with a society of professional
   historians, he is careful to distinguish study of a problem from that
   of a period in history. The latter, he agrees, requires the kind of
   "exhaustive treatment of all the material and a fair chronological
   distribution of the examination" that such historians are accustomed
   to. Dealing with a "problem," on the contrary, demands one follow
   other rules: "choice of the material in function of the givens of the
   problem; focus of one's analysis on the elements capable of resolving
   it; establishing the relations that allow this solution."[31]
   
   What he did not mention to the historians but spoke of elsewhere, as
   we noted above, and practiced even in his last works is the fact that
   the "solution" of a problem is the "displacement" of the question. It
   is the twin terms transformation and displacement that have governed
   Foucault's methods in all of his "histories." Both terms are intended
   to free our understanding of history from the "general, empty category
   of change," its "uniform model of temporalization" (AK 200) and
   traditional reliance on consciousness and subjectivity as well as from
   its dialectical subsumption of otherness and multiplicity in some
   overarching purpose or end.
   
   We have observed the transformation of medical perception in Birth of
   the Clinic, with its corresponding displacement of the object of
   medical investigation: of the body from occasion for the study of
   classes of disease to the individual body as site of abnormality.
   Discipline and Punish charts a similar transformation of discursive
   and nondiscursive practices of "inquisitorial" justice into those of
   "examinatory" justice that entailed "a displacement in the very object
   of the punitive operation .... Since it is no longer the body, it must
   be the soul" (DP 16). In effect, the offender and the guilty party are
   displaced by such objects of social science as the deviant and the
   delinquent. And this method continues in his "problemization" of
   sexual morality in the volumes published just before his death. He
   notes, for example, a transformation in fifth-century Athenian culture
   from a "stylistics of freedom" in which pleasure and its dynamic
   (chresis cphrodision) are the concern to the Socrato-Platonic erotic
   in which desire is directed to its true object, truth, by recognizing
   desire for what it is in its true being (see UP 267). The former asked
   a deontological question: What is the fitting and honorable thing to
   do?; the latter, an ontological one: What is love in is very being?
   This transformation of "ethics" (in Foucault's special sense of
   "practices of the self," "forms of subjectification") into a
   metaphysics entailed a corresponding displacement of the very object
   of discourse from the beloved and the honor of the loved one to the
   loving subject and the life of truth itself.[32] So the spatialized
   discourse of transformation-displacement continues to dominate
   Foucault's histories to the very end.
   
                                     V
                                      
   Stating a thesis with which we are now familiar, Foucault observed
   early in his career that, although for centuries writing had been
   ordered toward time, with Nietzsche we have "completed once for all
   the curve of Platonic memory and, with Joyce, closed the Homeric
   narrative." This situation "reveals that langugae is (or, perhaps, has
   become) something spatial (chose d'espace)."[33] Having surveyed the
   spaces of Foucault's histories (his nominalism forbids us to speak of
   "space" in the singular), let us conclude with some critical
   observations about this paradigm shift and its import for human
   history.
   
   One immediate consequence of this change is the undermining of
   universal history which, like the universal intellectual (see PK 126),
   must give way to a plurality of regional studies. Though he is the
   adversary of speculative philosophers of history, Foucault has never
   claimed that his approach should be anything more than complementary
   to more commonly pursued types of empirical history. Indeed, he has
   insisted that the archaeological description of discourses "is
   deployed in the dimension of a general history; it seeks to discover
   the whole domain of institutions, economic processes, and social
   relations on which a discursive formation can be articulated; it tries
   to show how the autonomy of discourse . . . [does] not give it the
   status of pure ideality and total historical independence" (AK 165).
   Unlike universal history, general history does not attempt to set the
   telos of the human adventure or measure its advance. The
   interdependence of discursive and nondiscursive practices as well as
   their inscription in a broad general history is even more obvious in
   his genealogies and especially his "problemizations," which in fact
   resemble traditional history of ideas far more than Foucault seemed
   willing to admit.
   
   Another victim of Foucault' s spatialization of historical language is
   appeal to historical accounts in terms of the ideology/science
   dichotomy preferred by Marxists and others. Not only is the
   distinction itself suspect, given the relativity of what counts as
   science to a particular epistemic grid and the questionable notion of
   truth implicit in the distinction, but the "political anatomy" or
   "geopolitics" that genealogy constructs renders "false consciousness,"
   "infrastructure," and other categories of ideologyanalysis trite and
   unconvincing.
   
   Spatialized discourse yields a history of "bodies" and not of
   "mentalities." Like Sartre before him, Foucault is an enemy of the
   inner life as well as its "exteriorization" in cultural objects and
   events. The constitution of the moral self, the formation of a class
   of delinquents, the alteration of our perception of diseased
   subjects--all refer to the disposition of bodies both in relation to
   one another and with regard to themselves (the self control, for
   example, of the moral agent). So appeal to strategy and the model of
   warfare rather than to meaning and intention is quite consistent with
   this subtle form of materialism. Working on the "surface" of things,
   Foucault displaces metaphysics with a "topology" of social practices,
   charting the limits, exclusions and specific "conditions of existence"
   of these practices in their actual occurrence.
   
   Accordingly, Foucault argues, "the coherence of such a history does
   not derive from the revelation of a project but from a logic of
   opposing strategies" (PK 61). Now this is a nondialectical "logic" in
   that it is neither reductive of multiplicity nor totalizing. "As
   always with relations of power," he notes, "one is faced with complex
   phenomena which don't obey the Hegelian form of the dialectic" (PK
   56). It is in this context that he speaks of the intellectual's
   providing us a "topological and geological survey of the battlefield"
   (PK 62).
   
   Perhaps the most controversial aspect of the spatialization of history
   is its freeing of the discipline from its moorings in philosophical
   anthropology, the famous "death of man" that caused so much ink to
   spill after the appearance of The Order of Things. Speaking of
   archaeology as "diagnosis," Foucault claims that it "does not
   establish the fact of our identity by the play of distinctions.
   [Rather], it establishes that we are difference, that our reason is
   the difference of discourses, our history the difference of times, our
   selves the difference of masks. That difference," he concludes, "far
   from being the forgotten and recovered origin, is this dispersion that
   we are and make" (AK 131). A condition of the existence of this
   dispersion is spatialized language that dissolves the unity of the
   self, dissipates projects by chance events and multiplies
   rationalities.
   
   But such a radical undertaking, a counter-history, as we have termed
   it, is not without its difficulties. One problem is precisely its
   derivative nature. It depends heavily upon traditional historical
   scholarship, the conceptual framework of which it often questions. How
   this counter-history stands to the facts it organizes is unclear,
   especially since Foucault seems to subscribe to the Nietzschean
   refusal of brute, uncontextualized facts. To the extent that it is
   "positivistic," it is subject to the falsification of its claims by
   contrary empirical evidence. And this counter-evidence has not been
   slow in emerging.[34]
   
   Yet there is something of the poet in Foucault's easy way with
   striking examples at the price of tedious factual corroboration.
   Indeed, in a famous phrase he once avowed: "I am well aware that I
   have not written anything but fictions" (PK 193)--which is not to say
   they have nothing to do with the truth. The price of being an
   historian suo modo is that he is not entirely at home either with
   professional historians or with philosophers. Arguably, his greatest
   influence to date has been with people working in literature and in
   the social sciences.
   
   The concept of counter-history underscores the power/knowledge dyad
   that came to dominate Foucault's thought. Pure, disinterested inquiry
   is impossible, he is saying; we must look for the uses to which a
   concept, hypothesis or theory is being put, not just individually but
   as part of an "economy" of warrants and justifications. But this
   applies to Foucault's own claims, which, despite the rationalistic
   rhetoric, are put forth as hypotheses themselves. Each of his
   "histories" is a local investigation and an exercise of power against
   the "lines of fracture," the veiled lineage, the presumed limit. Is he
   not subject to the debilitating paradox of selfreference, the bane of
   relativists? Rather than flee the objection, he seems to embrace it
   fully. The paradox is debilitating only for someone committed to a
   quasi-platonic objectivity or universality of concepts. If one's
   claims and expectations are more modest, one needn't sink in the mire
   of total relativism, a lesson we've known at least since Dewey.[35]
   
   Another problem concerns the specific "logic" of spatialized language.
   As Edward Said points out, what Foucault offers us by way of
   "argument" is adjacency, not sequentiality. Indeed, that is the
   significance of his using the image of the theatre to describe the
   exchange between philosophy and history that his work exhibits.[36]
   Now this is not necessarily a weakness; it's the mode of argument of
   the geographer and often of the social theorist. But whether it
   justifies the banner of "history," is another matter, which brings us
   to our final problem.
   
   The greatest difficulty with the spatialization of languge in general
   and of history in particular is the recalcitrance of the temporal in
   human activity. To the extent that Foucault retains a place for
   practice, he has saved a spot for temporality as well. Pierre Bourdieu
   has remarked in another context that "to substitute strategy for rule
   is to reintroduce time, with its rhythm, its orientation, its
   irreversibility" into the consideration. Although it is not clear that
   Foucault ever respected this temporal rhythm, let alone its
   "irreversibility," he valued the dispersive power of time implicit in
   his appeal to "practice" over "structure" (rule).[37] Strategy figures
   centrally in his genealogies and so by implication does time. The same
   might be said of the temporal rhythms of "style" that comes to
   dominate his last works. What Foucault's spatialization of language
   does to temporality is dislodge it from its central, unifying function
   in totalizing histories and existential projects. It restores to time
   its power of multiplicity, its differential weight, its Dionysian
   character. But it does so at a price: whether history as the narrative
   of human action can withstand this dispersion is questionable. But if
   not human action, what of freedom and moral life? Is an aesthetics of
   existence a reasonable alternative to these? Or is Ricoeur perhaps
   right after all--you cannot write a history without appealing to our
   pretheoretical experience of the temporal.
   
   Paul Veyne once repeated Jacques Maritain's observation that
   historians ultimately acquire "a sane philosophy of man" (WH 156).
   Whether as presupposition or product, a theoretical understanding of
   human nature is operative in Foucualt's thought: "man" as the object
   of the social sciences and their justification is fragmented into "the
   dispersion which we are." This "counter-anthropology" is the
   concomitant of his counter-history, each expressed and fostered by the
   spatialized language they employ. But whether it is "sane" or not is
   precisely the kind of normative question Foucault would insist we
   answer contextually.
   
                                   NOTES
                                      
   [1]. Michel Foucault, Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews & Other
   Writings, 1972-1977, ed. Colin Gordon (New York: Pantheon Books,
   1980), p. 70, hereafter cited as P K.
   
   [2]. This characterization was first made by his friend, Paul Veyne,
   in an appendix to the latter's Comment on ecrit l'histoire, entitled
   "Foucault revolutionne l'histoire" (Paris: Seuil, collection Points,
   1971 and 1978 respectively), p. 225. The main text is translated by
   Mina Moore-Rinvolucri as Writing History (Middletown, CT: Wesleyan
   University Press, 1974). I shall cite the main text in its English
   translation as WH and the untranslated appendix as FRH.
   
   [3]. See "What is Enlightenment?" in The Foucault Reader, ed. Paul
   Rabinow (New York: Pantheon Books, 1984), pp. 42 ff.
   
   [4]. His argument in distilled form is presented in the 1978-79
   Zaharoff Lecture, "The Contribution of French Historiography to the
   Theory of History" (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980) and at far greater
   length, though scarcely less concentrated, in his Time and Narrative,
   3 vols. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984-88), hereafter
   cited as TN.
   
   [5]. It may or may not be assuring to sociologists that Veyne concedes
   that "we are disputing the flag and not the goods" (WH 271). He
   insists, for example, that "the work of Max Weber... is truly history"
   (WH 287).
   
   [6]. From the blurb for the English translation.
   
   [7]. The matter is complex. For example, Veyne insists: "Every
   historical account is a plot out of which it would be artificial to
   cut discrete causes, and this account is directly causal,
   comprehensible; only the comprehension it gets is more or less deep"
   (WH 93). "Facts do not exist in isolation, in the sense that the
   fabric of history is what we shall call a plot, a very human and not
   very `scientific' mixture of material causes, aims, and chances--a
   slice of life, in short, that the historian cuts as he wills and in
   which facts have their objective connections and their relative
   importance ..." (WH 32).
   
   Michel de Certeau argues that Foucault's "stories" are, indeed, the
   inevitable form of any "theory of practices" as exemplified in
   Discipline and Punish and elsewhere. For he defends the hypothesis
   that "a narrative theory [is] indissociable from any theory of
   practices, for it [is] its precondition as well as its production"
   ("Micro-techniques and Panoptic Discourse" in Michel de Certeau
   Heterologies. Discourse on the Other [Minneapolis, MN: University of
   Minnesota Press, 1986], p. 192).
   
   On the other hand, Edward Said sees Foucault's method as
   "postnarrative," as testifying to "an active search.., for a
   nonnarrative way of dealing with nonnarratable units of knowledge"
   (Edward W. Said, Beginnings [Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University
   Press, 1975], p. 282). The contradiction is resolved if one extracts
   temporal sucession and subjectivity from narrative, leaving something
   akin to Veyne's "plot." But, as I shall argue in the concluding
   section of this essay, that may not suffice for a "theory of
   practices."
   
   [8]. Thus he describes his study of the prison system in the
   nineteenth century as a "history of the present" (Discipline and
   Punish, trans. Alan Sheridan [New York: Pantheon, 19771, p. 31,
   hereafter DP).
   
   Contrasting modern philosophy with more traditional philosophical
   concerns about permanence and change, mortality and immortality,
   Foucault remarks: "h seems to me that, since the nineteenth century,
   philosophy has not ceased asking itself the same question: `What is
   happening right now, and what are we, we who are perhaps nothing more
   than what is happening at this moment?' Philosophy's question is the
   question of the present age which is ourselves. This is why philosophy
   is today entirely political and entirely historical. It is the
   politics immanent in history and the history indispensable for
   politics" ("End of the Monarchy of Sex," Foucault Live, ed. Sylvere
   Lotringer [New York: Semiotext(e), 1989], p. 151, hereafter cited as
   FL).
   
   Foucault first finds this modern understanding of philosophy in Kant's
   What is Enlightenment? and he wonders whether one of the principal
   tasks of philosophy since then should not be characterized as "to
   describe the nature of the present and of `ourselves in the present'
   "(Michel Foucault, Politics, Philosophy, Culture. Interviews and Other
   Writings, 1977-1984, ed. Lawrence D. Kritzman [New York: Routledge,
   1988], p. 36, hereafter cited as PPC).
   
   [9]. See Ferdinand de Saussure, Course in General Linguistics, trans.
   Wade Baskin (New York: The Philosophical Library, 1959), p. 121.
   Specifically, Foucault in the Preface to his The Birth of the Clinic,
   after criticizing the tradition of commentary that has "doomed us
   historically to history, to the patient construction of discourses
   about discourses, and to the task of hearing what has already been
   said," recommends a "structural analysis of discourses that would
   evade the fate of commentary .... The meaning of a statement would be
   defined not by the treasure of intentions that it might contain,
   revealing and concealing it at the same time, but by the difference
   that articulates it upon the other real or possible statements, which
   are contemporary to it or to which it is opposed in the linear series
   of time. A systematic history of discourses would then become
   possible" (Birth of the Clinic, trans. A.M. Sheridan Smith [New York:
   Random House Vintage Books, 1975], pp. xvi-xvii, hereafter cited as
   BC).
   
   In view of such remarks by Foucault, it is difficult to justify the
   claim by Francois Wahl quoted with approval by Allan Magill that
   "Foucault makes no use of the Saussurean conception of difference"
   (Prophets of Extremity [Berkeley, CA: University of California Press,
   1985], p. 211).
   
   [10]. "The Discourse on Language," published as an appendix to The
   Archaeology of Knowledge, trans. A.M. Sheridan Smith (New York: Harper
   Colophon Books, 1972), p. 235, hereafter cited as AK. The concept of
   the historicity of science as a discontinuous series of
   epistemological "breaks" is, of course, the contribution of Foucault's
   model, Gaston Bachelard, while he owes much of his distrust of
   superficial "precursors" to his mentor in the history of science,
   Georges Canguilhem. For a valuable assessment of his intellectual debt
   to both of these thinkers, see Gary Gutting, Michel Foucault's
   Archaeology of Scientific Reason (Cambridge: Cambridge University
   Press, 1989), ch. I.
   
   [11]. Ferdinand de Saussure, Course, p. 121.
   
   [12]. "An Historian of Culture," in Foucault Live, p. 74.
   
   [13]. See my "Foucault and Historical Nominalism," in Harold A. Durfee
   and David F. T. Rodier, eds., Phenomenology and Beyond.' The Self and
   Its Languages (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1989), pp. 134--47.
   
   [14]. "Theatrum Philosophicum" in Michel Foucault, Language,
   CounterMemory, Practice, ed. Donald F. Bouchard (Ithaca, NY: Cornell
   University Press, 1977), pp. 185-86, hereafter cited as LCP.
   
   [15]. In a manner reminiscent of Sartre's existential humanism,
   Foucault avows: "I am simply saying: as soon as there is a power
   relation, there is the possibility of resistance. We are never trapped
   by power: we can always modify its grip in deter minate conditions and
   according to a precise strategy" ("End of the Monarchy of Sex," in
   Foucault Live, p. 153).
   
   [16]. Michel Foucault, "Des espaces autres,"
   Architecture-Mouvement-Continuite 5 (October 1984), pp. 46-49. A
   lecture delivered on March 14, 1967.
   
   [17]. Michel Foucault, Politics, .Philosophy, Culture. Interviews and
   Other Writings, 1977-1984, ed. Lawrence D. Kritzman (New York:
   Routledge, 1988), p. hereafter cited as PPC.
   
   [18]. Michel Foucault, "La Pensee du dehors," Critique 229 (June
   1966), 529. Anyone pursuing this "spatialization" of language in the
   literary realm must consider the writings of Maurice Blanchot.
   
   [19]. Foucault, "Penske," p. 545.
   
   [20]. I have explained elsewhere that by "practice" Foucault means in
   general "a preconceptual, anonymous, socially sanctioned body of rules
   that govern one's manner of perceiving, judging, imaging and acting. A
   practice forms the intelligble background for actions by its twofold
   character as judicative and "veridicative." "That is, on the one hand,
   practices establish and apply norms, controls and exclusions; on the
   other, they render true/false discourse possible. Thus the practice of
   legal punishment, for example, entails the interplay between a "code"
   that regulates the ways of acting--how to discipline an inmate, for
   example--and the production of true discourse which legitimates these
   ways of acting. The famous power/ knowledge dyad in Foucault's general
   schema merely denotes respectively these judicative and veridicative
   dimensions of 'practice'" ("Foucault and Historical Nominalism,"
   Phenomenology and Beyond, p. 135).
   
   [21]. See James W. Bernauer, Michel Foucault's Force of Flight
   (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1990), pp. 109-10.
   
   [22]. "End of the Monarchy of Sex," in Foucault Live, p. 138.
   
   [23]. Michel Foucault, "Nietzsche, Genealogy, History," in LCP,
   154-55, translation modified.
   
   [24]. Francois Ewald, "Anatomie et corps politique," Critique 343
   (1975), p. 1229. 25. Allan Megill, Prophets of Extremity, p. 238.
   
   [26]. See my "Foucault as Parrhesiast: His Last Course at the College
   de France," in James Bernauer and David Rasmussen eds., The Final
   Foucault (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1988). 102-18.
   
   [27]. Interview with Francois Ewald, "Le Souci de la verite," Magazine
   Litteraire, 207 (May 1984), p. 22.
   
   [28]. "Truth and Subjectivation in the Later Foucault," The Journal of
   Philosophy 82/10 (Oct. 1985), 532.
   
   [29]. Michel Foucault, Histoire de la sexualite, vol. 2: L 'Usage des
   plaisirs (Paris: Gallimard, 1984), p. 12, hereafter cited as UP.
   
   [30]. Interview with Francois Ewald, "Le Souci de la verite," p. 22.
   
   [31]. Michelle Perrot, ed., L'Impossible Prison (Paris: Editions du
   Seuil, 1980), p. 32, hereafter cited as IP.
   
   [32]. See my "Truth and Subjectivation in the Later Foucault," p. 535.
   
   [33]. Michel Foucault, "Le Language de l'espace," Critique 203 (April,
   1964), 378.
   
   [34]. See, for example, Jacques Proust et al., "Entretiens sur
   Foucault," La Penske 137 (February 1968), 4-37, as well as Gutting,
   Michel Foucault's Archaeology of Scientific Reason, pp. 175 ff.
   
   [35]. See my "Foucault and the Politics of Postmodernity," Nous 23/2
   (April 1989), especially pp. 196-97.
   
   [36]. See Edward W. Said, Beginnings, pp. 302 and 291-92.
   
   [37]. Pierre Bourdieu, Outline of a Theory of Practice, trans. Richard
   Nice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977), p. 9.
   
   ~~~~~~~~
   
   By Thomas R. Flynn, Emory University
                             _________________
   
   Copyright of Monist is the property of Hegeler Institute and its
   content may not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a
   listserv without the copyright holder's express written permission.
   However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual
   use.
   Source: Monist, Apr91, Vol. 74 Issue 2, p165, 22p.
   Item Number: 9705284633
   

Link to Foucault Page
Kindly click here to return to Foucault Page

Kindly click here to return to Academic Interests
Please click here to return to Additional Information

page last updated 28 October 2004
Copyright © 2004 Miguel B. Llora, MA. All Rights Reserved.
Best viewed on Internet Explorer 5.x or later at a minimum of 1024 x 768 resolution