Magazine: Social Research, Summer, 1994



   Title: Thinking beyond the East-West divide: Foucault, Patocka, and

   the care of the self.

   Subject(s): PATOCKA, Jan -- Criticism & interpretation; FOUCAULT,

   Michel -- Criticism & interpretation; SELF (Philosophy); POLITICAL

   science -- Philosophy

   Source: Social Research, Summer94, Vol. 61 Issue 2, p297, 27p

   Author(s): Szakolczai, Arpad

   Abstract: Examines the works of Czech philosopher Jan Patocka in

   relation to Foucault's works about the transformation of the self and

   its link to politics. Patocka's reliance upon personal experiences and

   reflections on his earlier work; Patocka's involvement in politics

   during his later years; Foucault's first-hand knowledge of Eastern

   Europe; Common preoccupations between Patocka and Foucault.

   AN: 9410115869

   ISSN: 0037-783X

   Full Text Word Count: 9061

   Database: Academic Search Elite

   

   THINKING BEYOND THE EAST-WEST DIVIDE: FOUCAULT, PATOCKA, AND THE CARE

                                OF THE SELF

                                      

                                Introduction

                                      

   FOR decades now, Foucault's work has elicited all sorts of

   controversy. This controversy, however, contains one constant element

   shared by all participants--they all focus on the books written in the

   1970's, the works which are most widely read and are usually

   associated with his name.[1] Unfortunately, much less attention is

   paid to his later works, which focus on the question of the self and

   subjectivity. Because Foucault was constantly revisiting the same

   themes, trying both to distance himself from his earlier statements

   and at the same time to refine his approach, it is reasonable to

   expect that his later work has much to say about his earlier work.

   This is especially so in his last years, when Foucault was explicitly

   using reflection upon his former writings, a work upon his own work,

   as a strategy to overcome his crisis and gain momentum in research.[2]

   The relative neglect of this later work is all the more surprising as

   the problem of the self returned to the center of interest in

   political theory.[3] Foucault's name in fact does appear in this

   debate,[4] but the discussion is firmly rooted on both sides of the

   controversy surrounding it in the perspective he provided in the books

   of the mid-1970s.

   

   Two significant recent contributions further support this claim of

   neglect. The first are two articles written by Mark Warren that

   reintroduce the concept of self-transformation into the literature on

   participatory democracy (Warren, 1992, 1993). The idea of the

   transformation of the self and its link to politics was at the center

   of Foucault's interest during his late period. Although Warren

   discusses Discipline and Punish, he fails to mention any of Foucault's

   later work. The second contribution is a book by Fred Alford that

   attempts to bring together the conceptualization of the self in

   political philosophy, analyzing Plato, Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau, and

   Rawls, and the psychoanalytic approach of Kohut and Lacan (Alford,

   1991). Alford briefly alludes to Foucault's work, specifically the

   Vermont seminars, considering them as the exposition of a short

   research program (Alford, 1991, p. 21). The topic of these seminars,

   however, was not the outline of a future research project but rather a

   short summary of work previously done. Though the whole work did

   remain unfinished, large portions have been presented in lectures

   delivered at the College de France and elsewhere.[5] One obvious

   reason why Foucault's late work is little known is that much of the

   material is still unpublished. However, without going into the highly

   controversial topic of posthumous publications, in these lectures

   Foucault did in fact publicly present his own work. It is available,

   on tape or sometimes in a typescript version, in the Foucault Archives

   in Paris. Therefore, it is not only the supply that is missing, but

   there seems to be a problem with demand as well.

   

   The use of Foucault's late writings, and indeed of the whole of his

   work, could be much helped by situating them in a proper context.

   Though Foucault's work regularly appears in a number of contemporary

   debates (post-modernism, post-structuralism, or post-Marxism) and is

   contrasted or compared with that of other thinkers (Habermas, Deleuze,

   Derrida, or Lyotard), these' references fail to appreciate the

   difference Foucault's work made with respect to these approaches.

   Weber or Elias look much more promising, and there is some work done

   along these lines.[6] But none of the presumed connections is

   stronger, more direct and perplexing, than the elective affinities

   that exist between the works of Foucault and the Czech philosopher Jan

   Patocka, especially as relates to the concept of the care of the self.

   Until now, this connection has gone unnoticed.[7] The purpose of this

   article is to introduce the works of Patocka into the discussion on

   Foucault in order to give this literature a novel angle and also to

   increase interest in the detailed study of the last period of

   Foucault's work.

   

                        Jan Patocka: Life and Works

                                      

   As Patocka's name is little known outside the small circle of experts

   on East-Central European politics and philosophy, a short account must

   be given of his life and work. In the presentation, special emphasis

   will be placed on Patocka's reliance upon personal experiences and

   reflections on his earlier work in developing his project and driving

   it toward completion.

   

   Jan Patocka (1907-1977) as a philosopher is virtually unknown both in

   England and the United States; there are few English publications of

   his works.[8] If his name sounds somewhat familiar, however, it is

   because of his death, not his life and work. In 1977, he became one of

   the three spokesmen of Charter 77. After being subjected to exhaustive

   police investigations, he developed cardiac problems and died in early

   March of that year. This and the concept of "living in truth" Havel

   took from Patocka became standard themes in the literature on East

   European dissidence. Paradoxically, these tributes to Patocka and the

   association of his name with moralism and anti-politics made him look

   more like a respectable person, though too much of an idealist, than

   an original thinker.[9]

   

   Patocka's work is more recognized in continental Europe. For instance,

   his complete works are translated into German, and in France most of

   his writings have appeared since 1981 and are widely read and

   discussed by phenomenologists. In fact, he seems to be the only East

   European thinker who, solely on the basis of work accomplished behind

   the Iron Curtain, receives serious contemporary attention.[10]

   

   Patocka was born and raised in a typical East-Central European elite

   intellectual milieu.[11] After receiving his first university degree

   in Prague, he continued his studies in Paris; he was fortunate to be

   there when Husserl delivered his famous lectures. On defending his

   thesis in Prague on "The Concept of Evidence and its Significance for

   Noetics," he went abroad again, first to Berlin in 1932-33 and then to

   Freiburg, in order to study with Husserl and also to become acquainted

   with Heidegger. These years were crucial for him not only for academic

   reasons, but also for the exposure and experience he received in

   politics.

   

   A full-scale existential transformation followed. In an interview

   given and published in 1967, he described his return to Prague in 1934

   with the following words: "When I returned to Czechoslovakia with all

   these [ideas] I was almost completely isolated, and hardly anyone

   succeeded to understand what I wanted, even my friends from my

   generation with whom I was strongly related, and who to a large extent

   were more able than me" (Patocka, 1981, p. 170).[12] He settled down

   when he met emigrants from Nazi Germany and organized a philosophical

   circle with them. This activity was suspended by the Munich treaty of

   1938.

   

   In 1936, Patocka defended his habilitation thesis on the "Natural

   World," but due to the economic crisis, he failed to obtain a

   university position. He got his chance after the war. Between 1945 and

   1949, realizing long-cherished plans, he taught four courses on the

   origins of philosophy dealing with the pre-Socratics, Socrates, Plato,

   and Aristotle. He was preparing a comprehensive work on the basis of

   his lecture notes when the Communist takeover occurred in 1948-49.

   

   Patocka was dismissed from the University and was not allowed to

   publish. He found refuge first at the Masaryk Institute as an

   archivist and then at the Comenius Archives. At first he continued his

   work, and in the early '50s he wrote "Negative Platonism," one of his

   most significant writings that was intended as part of a larger

   project formulating his own philosophy.[13] This project, however, was

   never completed. Instead, using his meager but real possibilities,

   Patocka soon turned to those subject areas where he would have a

   chance for open work and publication, even at the price of temporarily

   giving up his own idiom: to the work of Comenius and the history of

   science.

   

   Doing so, Patocka did not just succumb to the limits imposed by the

   system. He simply took the existence of the Communist regime for

   granted as an externally imposed reality and tried to make the most of

   his work given this fact. The crucial point is that he continued

   working without making the slightest gestures toward the regime and

   without taking part in the favorite game of intellectuals and

   ideologues regarding the limits of the forbidden and permitted. Though

   this game may have contributed to the loosening and eventual demise of

   the system, it also had the lasting effect of making all participants

   dependent on it, unable to preserve autonomy and internal composure.

   The significant consequences of such in-depth personality

   transformations are only becoming visible today.

   

   It was in the mid-1960s that new opportunities opened up for Patocka.

   In 1964, he published a book on Aristotle, summarizing a decade of

   work. Soon he was allowed to lecture abroad on phenomenology. In 1966,

   he taught a course at Charles University about Husserl, Scheler, and

   Heidegger, and in 1968 he returned on a regular basis. But, more

   importantly, he was finally able to return to the work on his own

   philosophy that was interrupted in the early 1950s. This did not

   happen easily. A return to his former writings made it evident how

   much he had changed--a change that was made possible because he kept

   working, preserving his inner discipline. It was only in 1968-69 that

   he began to publish and to talk about the more general concepts of his

   philosophy and not simply to comment Hussefi and Heidegger.[14] At

   this point, for the fourth time, external politics again interfered

   with his work.

   

   This time, however, Patocka's answer was different. He was already

   over the age of sixty. His life was behind him, a life which he was

   now in a position to summarize. If he was not allowed to teach in

   public, he gave regular private seminars. If he was not allowed to

   publish, he circulated his works in samizdat.[15] The result was

   Patocka's most creative period. A first overview of his work, in the

   context of a private seminar on classical Greek philosophy, was given

   in the summer of 1973 (Patocka, 1983). Patocka then worked for two

   years on a series of essays that were widely considered his chef

   d'oeuvre (Patocka, 1981a).

   

   After these accomplishments, Patocka returned to phenomenology in

   order to find out where Husserl went wrong. But this was not the best

   known or even the most important part of his last activities. As he

   approached the age of seventy, Patocka did something he had never done

   before: he became directly involved in politics. The decision

   represented a break with everything he had done before in public.

   Still, this move was not sudden but was carefully premeditated, as

   shown by the text of the crucial Varna lecture Patocka gave in

   1972.[16] After decades of unceasing personal work and the

   accomplishment of what could be called, after Nietzsche, his "task,"

   after a life spent with rigorous and unegoistic "care with the soul,"

   Patocka thought the time had come to care directly for others by an

   act of sacrifice so that they would care for themselves.

   

               Links Between Foucault's and Patocka's Thought

                                      

   On a first look, the lives and works of Patocka and Foucault seem to

   be very different, even opposed. Patocka lived in the East under an

   overtly repressive political regime. Foucault was a Western thinker

   trying to come to terms with much subtler mechanisms of controlling

   and shaping individuals. Patocka was a phenomenologist, a disciple of

   Husserl, while Foucault singled out phenomenology as the line of

   investigation to which he was most opposed.[17] Patocka was a

   philosopher in the classical sense of the term, while Foucault long

   rejected such an identification.

   

   This apparent mutual neglect and opposition between them seems to have

   been the standard reception perspective on the relationship between

   the two.[18] Yet, on a more careful look, the oppositions begin to

   falter. First, Foucault did have some first-hand knowledge of East

   Europe. He spent the year 1958-59 in Warsaw, wrote most of Madness and

   Civilisation there, and considered the experience crucial.[19] Second,

   Foucault's hostility toward phenomenology should be qualified. While

   Patocka's whole work revolved around Husserl and Heidegger, Foucault's

   first publication, an "Introduction" to Dream and Existence by Ludwig

   Binswanger, a Heideggerian psychoanalyst, contained several references

   to Husserl. In an important piece detailing his intellectual

   trajectory, Foucault starts the account with Husserl, considering him

   the starting point of both contemporary French and German philosophy;

   and in his last interview, he discussed in depth the profound

   importance Heidegger had on his thoughts (Foucault, 1978b; 1988b, pp.

   242-54). What he was most opposed to in phenomenology was the idea of

   the transcendental subject, but, in fact, this was also at the heart

   of Patocka's critique of Husserl; in his last years Patocka followed

   Heidegger much more than Husserl just as Foucault was using Heidegger

   in his courses given between 1980 and 1984.[20] Finally, there is a

   strong similarity between the ideal of the philosophic life in Patocka

   and Foucault.

   

   Thus, it is easier to understand why some of the key ideas of Foucault

   and Patocka are perplexingly close. Both were much concerned with the

   way their work could be connected to the present and were conscious

   about effects. Their attitude can be characterized by two common

   preoccupations. First, their aim was to question the "taken for

   granted," to shake evidences. To this end, Patocka talks about "the

   enormous task of the revision and destruction of all 'evidences',"

   while Foucault talks about the "unmaking of evidences," of those

   subtle moments when "evidences are lost," and even the lesson of

   Merleau-Ponty, according to whom "the essential philosophical task is

   never to consent completely to one's own evidences" (Patocka, 1985,

   pp. 137-38; Foucault, 1979a, pp. 82-3).[21] Second, they intended to

   take this line of questioning to the limit, not shying away from

   dangers--not just in the evident political sense but concerning the

   most cherished views and assumptions one holds.[22]

   

   If their joint aim was an in-depth analysis of the present, of our

   "taken-for-granted" reality, they also chose an identical and not

   self-evident manner to analyze the present: doing reconstructive

   studies in history. Though the concrete areas of investigation were

   often quite different, the strategy of research was the same. They

   were not trying to read solutions from history but were concerned with

   questions and problems. According to Patocka, history began with the

   discovery of problematicity; Foucault stated in his last year that the

   common notion of all his work was a conception of history (or the

   history of thought) as problematization[23]

   

   Not only the modality of their approach to history was identical but

   also the main topic. Foucault often defined his work as a "history of

   truth" or a "history (or genealogy) of subjectivity." Beginning in the

   1980s, he also stated that the general problem underlying his work is

   the question of the links between truth and subjectivity[24]

   "Subjectivity" and "truth" are also central terms for Patocka, and,

   just like for Foucault, the basic question is the exact link between

   the two terms. It is well-known that the concept "living in truth" was

   one of the most important concepts of Patocka, taken up by Havel and

   repeated ad nauseam by the literature on East European dissidence. But

   the question of truth-telling and of living in truth was the central

   preoccupation of Foucault in his last two years at the College de

   France. In one of the last lectures, he even made

   the--tentative--remark that a topic he would like to cover the

   following year, but for which he still did not feel up to, was the

   question of the "true life."[25]

   

   The question of subjectivity and the links between truth and

   subjectivity have a dual role in the works of Patocka and Foucault.

   The first concerns the role of subject in modern philosophy. They

   agree in a critique of the subjectivist turn and in the assessment of

   Husserl. Even for Patocka Husserl never managed to overcome the

   concept of transcendental subjectivity, in spite of his late attempt

   in this direction with the concepts of "intersubjectivity" and

   "life-world," concepts which Patocka, in contradistinction to

   Habermas, considered still inadequate (Patocka, 1989a, pp. 223-38;

   1989b, pp. 285-326; 1988, pp. 189-215). But, second, linking truth and

   subjectivity was not simply an abstract matter for them, but something

   which, for better or worse, they also tried to pursue in their lives.

   They were certainly not just professional philosophers, though their

   extreme erudition is mentioned by everyone who knew them closely; they

   tried to live a philosophical life in the old, classical, original

   Socratic sense.[26]

   

   Finally, the manner in which the unity of such a philosophical life

   and work could be realized was also the same in both cases. It was

   identical in terms of statements, the emphasis laid on a life of

   relentless work, a life of ascesis and discipline. Thus, for Patocka,

   "culture is a work, it is an ascesis"; for Foucault, philosophy is

   work, "an "ascesis," an exercise of oneself in the activity of

   thought" (Patocka, 1991, p. 194; Foucault, 1986, p. 9). And both

   Patocka and Foucault did in fact live their lives according to this

   ideal.

   

   It should be repeated that these points are both specific to and

   crucial for the works of Foucault and Patocka. However, of all

   commonalities, nothing is more central than the concept of the care of

   the soul, or the self.

   

                      Patocka and the Care of the Soul

                                      

   The care of the soul (le soin de l'ame) was not simply a concept used

   by Patocka but his most important one. It is the guiding theme of his

   last two summary works, Plato and Europe and The Heretical Essays, and

   has been selected as the title of the six-volume samizdat edition of

   his collected works.[27] Patocka makes rather strong claims for the

   general importance of this concept: it is the care of the soul that is

   the central element in the heritage of Europe. The destiny of Europe,

   or Western civilization, is linked to the fate of the care of the

   soul.

   

   This is not just an isolated remark but returns, and is stressed,

   throughout Plato and Europe. Most of the individual chapters, or

   seminars, close with a reference to the link between the care of the

   soul and Europe. The care of the soul is "at the basis of the European

   heritage" (Patocka, 1983, p. 21). "The history of Europe, in a great

   part, up to about the fifteenth century, is the history of attempts

   made to realize the care of the soul" (1983, p. 45). "What is

   constituted here, with this philosophy of the care of the soul, will

   make the specificity of the European [form of] life. . . . [here lies]

   not just the specificity, the autonomy, but also the continuity of the

   European [form of] life. . . . Europe as Europe was born out of the

   theme of the care of the soul" (1983, p. 79). "Europe--Western Europe

   first of all, but also what is called the "other Europe"--is issued

   from the care of the soul" (1983, p. 99). The list could be continued.

   

   These formulations are summed up in the last seminar:

   

   The task we set for ourselves was to reflect upon the beginning of

          history. Now, history is the history of Europe, there is no

          other one. The rest of the world knows annals, historiography,

          but not the continuity of an unitary mission, susceptible of

          universalisation. And what is at the source of European

          history? We have said that it is the idea of the care of the

          soul, the idea in which there are reflexively summed up all the

          aspirations of Europe up to the present (1983, p. 225).

          

   The Heretical Essays take up and elaborate on the same theme: "The

   care of the soul is . . . what gave birth to Europe--we can maintain

   this thesis without the slightest exaggeration" (Patocka, 1981, p.

   93).

   

   Such statements should strike any Western social scientist as

   incredibly naive: a peculiar mixture of Hegelian idealism and early

   modernization theories. And yet Patocka realizes the stakes of his

   claims. That is why he states so unequivocally "without the slightest

   exaggeration." And that is why he takes the trouble of qualifying

   carefully, once the radicality of the claims is maintained, both

   controversial elements: the reality as opposed to the idealism of the

   concept and the unique position of Europe.

   

   First, Patocka repeatedly stresses that his is not an idealist thesis

   (Patocka, 1983, p. 79). First, the care of the soul is not an

   autonomous mental activity but a specific practice, "the praxis of

   intellectual life" (Patocka, 1981, p. 92). This practice is a

   reflection on what one is actually doing, leaving a mark on all

   activities. The care of the soul "enters in the circle of all other

   human possibilities and . . . obliges [them] to reflect. In this way,

   it leads even what is not philosophic to a degree and state different

   from where it was before the reflection" (1983, p. 79). But, second,

   the care of the soul is not just a correlate but a direct activity, a

   work on the agent that is able to effectuate reflection: the soul. In

   order to perform its task, the soul must guard its own forces, must be

   vigilant and wakeful: "So that we could effectuate this brand new and,

   in a sense, pitiless work of thought, there must be a discipline of

   the soul, we have to take care of the soul" (1983, p. 87). The care of

   the soul is not just a universal lateral activity but first of all

   involves taking care of itself.

   

   Finally, this practice of the care of the soul has a specific target:

   truth. This was first just the correlate of Greek cosmology, as

   Patocka shows for the case of Democritos (1983, Ch. 5). With Socrates

   and Plato, however, a new demand emerges: truth, instead of being the

   intellectual condition of the soul that makes access to truth

   possible, becomes replaced by the stronger exigency of the true life.

   The crucial point of any philosophy of the care of the soul is the

   extent to which a philosopher validates his principles by his own

   life.

   

   The practice of the care of the soul emerged as a response given to a

   concrete challenge: This challenge, however, also has direct relevance

   for our own daily life. It is the link between these two moments in

   history that is at the center of Patocka's attention.

   

   Two possible paths can be chosen to study these links: one could start

   with the present, with us, on an involving, personal, and

   self-referential note, or one could start with the past, the moment of

   emergence, using the most detached and classical philosophical

   language. In his two main works, if only to indicate their

   complementarity, Patocka chose alternative paths, paying attention to

   the circumstances in which his ideas were put forward: the first, in

   Plato and Europe, a private seminar; the second, in The Heretical

   Essays, a wider audience.

   

   The Heretical Essays start with Patocka's reading of the Husserlian

   concept of the "natural world," or the Lebenswelt, used to describe a

   primary situation, the starting point of general analysis. This

   "natural world" was used by Heidegger, shifting the emphasis, as the

   background against which, according to the Greek word aletheia, truth

   became manifest. Patocka takes a further step. He claims that the

   problem that phenomenology set out for itself to solve, forming a

   precise description of this "natural world," is impossible: "the

   problem of the natural world does not seem for us susceptible to be

   resolved" (1981, p. 24). Instead of an exhaustive description, he opts

   for a negative definition: the natural world is the world before

   problematicity, that is, before history. He indexes the problem of the

   emergence of the manifestation of truth to the birth of history, the

   realization of problematicity.

   

   This specific configuration explains the sudden and joint emergence of

   three different but connected sets of concerns: the search for the

   order of the cosmos (cosmogony); the search for a stable political

   order (politics); and, finally, the search for internal stability

   (philosophy as the care of the soul). In this context, the specificity

   and significance of the new practice becomes visible. Philosophy is

   not simply reflection about the meaning of life or the order of the

   world; it is a practice to shape the soul (the self) not simply in

   order to attain an abstract and eternal truth but to realize a true

   life: a life that is stable, is able to withstand the loss of meaning,

   of disorder, without closing the opening of freedom and receding into

   an ossification of social and human existence.

   

   This practice of strengthening the soul proved to be extremely

   powerful and lasting. It was this practice that made the civilization

   in which it was born able to withstand a number of ensuing crises, the

   collapse of all those political projects that were defined

   correlatively with the philosophical practice of the care of the soul:

   the Greek polis, the Roman Empire, and, finally, the Holy Roman

   Empire. It was this practice that has been taken over by Christianity,

   providing it with its ground, so that it "represents the strive that

   is up to the present the most powerful--never surpassed, but never

   even thought until the end--that makes man capable of fighting against

   decay" (1981, p. 117).[28]

   

   At this point, Patocka qualifies his story with a surprising turn.

   Everything said about the destiny of the care of the soul and Europe

   holds true only up to a moment--the disruptions around the sixteenth

   century. It is with the beginning of the early modern period, however,

   with the period of science, discoveries, economic and colonial

   expansion, that Patocka locates the disappearance of the care of the

   soul, the moment of betrayal, the source of our present condition.

   

   This is where the private seminars take off, running the same circle

   from the other end. Patocka begins with a diagnosis on two levels,

   whose exact links are suspended. He elaborates on the environmental,

   political, economic crises of the present but even more on the

   dominant current mood, a sense of helplessness. This is what makes the

   situation truly intolerable, not the objective circumstances. This is

   the configuration that is comparable to the conditions of emergence of

   Europe; and this is the reason why as a way out he is proposing to

   re-launch the project: "The question that we will pose is the

   following: the care of the soul, that is at the basis of the European

   heritage, isn't today again for us to recur to, us who are in need of

   finding support amidst the general weakness and the resignation to

   decline?" (1983, p. 21).

   

   On stating Patocka's rather startling claims about the specificity of

   Europe, two possible charges were immediately voiced: idealism and

   Euro-centrism. We have seen that Patocka was well aware of these

   objections and was trying to anticipate and meet them. Still, his

   arguments need additional support. It is this reinforcement that is

   provided, however surprisingly, by a thinker hardly known to Patocka:

   Michel Foucault.

   

                     Foucault and the Care of the Self

                                      

   The care of the self (le souci de soi) was not just a concept used by

   Foucault but had a central place in his most important last period.

   First, it became the title of volume three of the sexuality series.

   This, in itself, should not be underestimated, as Foucault was always

   quite concerned with precise title selection. But there is more. He

   originally planned to publish the book outside the sexuality

   series.[29] It was supposed to be based on his 1982 course entitled

   "The Hermeneutics of the Subject," which was not at all about

   sexuality but which discussed the care of the self. In this course,

   Foucault was not just working on the theoretical and methodological

   problems related to the sexuality project, as was the case with the

   1980 course, but was already going beyond what he considered at that

   time burdensome homework and tried to tackle directly the broader

   question of the history of subjectivity.

   

   Second, this concept is not only similar but is identical to Patocka's

   "care of the soul." First, the Greek word used for "care" is identical

   in both thinkers. Patocka is using the Greek expression epimeleia tes

   psyches, while Foucault uses the phrase epimeleia heautou.[30] The

   second word is different but names the same thing. Patocka is

   emphasizing that in Plato, as opposed to the previous tradition, the

   soul is not simply the source of intellectual knowledge and truth as

   seen from the perspective of others but is the "soul that I am"

   (Patocka, 1983, pp. 78-9). Foucault, when analyzing the meaning of the

   term heautou, immediately shows that it is the "soul." At this point,

   his analysis must be presented in some detail.

   

   Foucault opens the first lecture of 1982 with three broad claims,

   situating the topic.[31] He begins with the distinction between the

   care of the self and the knowledge of oneself, putting the emphasis on

   the former as opposed to the standard reading of the history of

   philosophy. He then connects this tradition to Socrates. On the basis

   of three passages in the Apology, Foucault makes three points. First,

   the care of the self was the mission Socrates received from the

   gods--not caring for others but inciting them to care about

   themselves. Second, this poses the question of the link between the

   care for oneself and the ability of making others care for themselves.

   Third, the role of Socrates is restricted to the first moment, the

   awakening. The project which Foucault locates in Socrates and which he

   claims to lie at the heart of European philosophy is to wake others up

   from the slumber in which they conduct their everyday existence in

   order to live differently: not following any precept but starting to

   be concerned with themselves. The third main opening claim in the 1982

   lecture is that though this idea started with Socrates, it was not

   restricted to him but was widespread in ancient philosophy, and a

   number of different practices emerged related to it.

   

   In the second hour of the first lecture, Foucault starts his analysis

   by using Plato's Alcibiades as his source material, a text he called

   "the very theory" (la theorie meme) of the care of the self. According

   to Foucault, this text is divided into two parts, defining first the

   meaning of "self" and then of "care."[32] Concerning the first,

   Foucault starts with emphasizing the way Plato introduced the

   definition of the "self" into the dialogue; this starts with a second,

   stressed, reflexive, and elaborate reference to the famous Delphic

   statement, defining the mission of Socrates. Second, he states that

   the definition of the "self" is given quickly: it is the soul, defined

   as one's own soul. Third, the most important point in this definition,

   according to Foucault, is the way Plato arrives at the definition. It

   starts with a number of questions, indicating that the specificity of

   the soul is located in the act of questioning. The capacity of posing

   questions is located in language, the grammatical subject, and this

   subject is defined through the use of language as an instrument.

   Foucault is elaborating on the Greek word for use, chrestai, a term

   that will serve as the title of the second volume of the sexuality

   series. Finally, in this way, Plato arrives at the definition of the

   soul, which is, therefore, not a "soul-substance" linked to the

   problem of eternity and immortality but a "soul-subject" defining the

   singular and transcendent position of the subject in relation to what

   surrounds him.

   

   In specifying the meaning of heautou, a definition of its care is

   already implied. If the soul is the relation one has to the

   surroundings, then "care" defines its modality. The different

   expressions used in French or given in the English translations

   provide a good indication of this meaning of epimeleia: it is to take

   care of, to be concerned with, to take pains at. But this refers to

   the surroundings and not to the soul itself. The second part of the

   definition deals with the meaning of the care applied to the self. And

   here, according to Foucault, Plato is immediately evoking the

   principle of "know yourself," defining the soul as the divine in man.

   With this act, Platonic philosophy lapsed back into metaphysics and

   idealism.

   

   The rest of the 1982 course takes a clue from this claim, studying the

   resurgence of the care of the self in the Roman period, while a good

   part of the 1983 course represents a more nuanced reading of Plato.

   But, in the 1984 course, the problematics of the care of the self in

   Socrates returns in a slightly different form and with extreme

   emphasis (Foucault Archives, C 69 [3] and C 69 [4]).

   

   The death of Socrates, analyzed in the third lecture, is the

   paradigmatic starting point for the course, an introduction to

   Foucault's main concern: the connection of the 1982 and the 1983

   lectures, the care of the self and the telling of truth (parrhesia).

   This connection is made in the fourth lecture through an analysis of

   Laches. This, rather than Alcibiades, is the dialogue where Foucault

   now traces the tradition in philosophy to which he claims to belong.

   Its importance is shown by its position in the course and also spelled

   out explicitly by Foucault on several occasions.[33] And it is at that

   very point, at the end of the introductory remarks on Laches, that

   Foucault is making reference to a philosopher, the only philosopher

   who, according to him, read Plato and, therefore, European philosophy

   in the same manner. This philosopher is Patocka and specifically his

   book Plato and Europe.[34]

   

   Thus far, we have shown that the philosophies of Foucault and Patocka,

   far from being opposite, were rather mutually the closest. Our second

   point is that Foucault elaborated a concept that provided a crucial

   supplement to Patocka's work, establishing a solid ground against

   charges of idealism. This was the concept of the "techniques of self."

   

   The place of this concept is again crucial in Foucault's work. It has

   been emphasized in his most important methodological writing, the

   introduction of The Use of Pleasure, where the concepts

   problematization and techniques of self are singled out as the most

   important theoretical benefits gained through the carrying out of the

   sexuality project (Foucault, 1986, pp. 10-11). Foucault has defined

   this concept several times. Let us single out the one given in the

   Vermont seminars: "technologies of the self . . . permit individuals

   to effect by their own means or with the help of others a certain

   number of operations on their own bodies and souls, thoughts, conduct,

   and way of being, so as to transform themselves in order to attain a

   certain state of happiness, purity, wisdom, perfection, or

   immortality" (Foucault, 1988c, p. 10). The presence of these

   techniques permits something that has been central, in many different

   forms, in all the writings of Foucault: the shaping and the

   transformation of individuals. But this term, as opposed to the

   earlier term "techniques of power," also points out the specificity of

   such techniques in the West. They are never simply imposed or

   internalized forms of domination, but techniques that always involve

   and rely upon the very freedom of the individual as an agent in their

   operation, and which present opportunities that are not possible to

   eliminate. If, according to Patocka, the history of Europe is the

   history of the care of the self, then for Foucault, supporting and

   supplementing Patocka, the history of the West is the history of the

   way in which the techniques of self were used and deployed,

   "democratized," connected but never reducible to the systematization

   of the government of others. Far from being a category of post-modern

   aestheticism, as it is often alleged, Foucault's "care of the self"

   goes to the heart of Western rationality, precisely in the sense of

   Max Weber.[35] And far from being a category of Hegelian idealism,

   Patocka's "care of the soul" is as much in touch with reality as

   Foucault's most empirical and institutional undertakings.

   

                                 Conclusion

                                      

   This article has argued that the similarities between the works of

   Patocka and Foucault are extremely strong. They may be closer to each

   other than any other major post-war philosophers. This point is not

   exegetical. Direct links among them were minimal.[36] It is that both

   Foucault and Patocka independently tried to gain access to the heart

   of the present and with much success. This raises fundamental

   questions of method. How did all this become possible? What made

   Foucault and Patocka able to gain this insight? What can we learn

   about the proper conduct of research?

   

   The first thing Foucault and Patocka shared concerning their conduct

   of research was that it was personal.[37] This did not mean that they

   were only pronouncing personal opinions. Quite the contrary, personal

   research for them meant the opposite: the lonely, arduous pursuit of a

   singular, specific line of investigation; the study of a number of

   different, seemingly disparate themes. Instead of building up a theory

   or system or pronouncing subjective judgments, they did hard work on

   different texts, the connection between them often difficult to

   perceive. The first necessary condition for an access to the heart of

   the present, therefore, seems to be long, persistent, lonely, and

   isolated work, far from the noisy debates of the intellectual scene,

   far from the Habermasian public sphere that only leads to the

   reduction of all discussion to the smallest common denominator.

   

   But, second, this does not mean opting for narrow professional

   research. Distance from current debates does not necessarily lead to

   distance from the concerns of the present. Access to its heart for

   Foucault and Patocka was provided, paradoxically, by the pursuit and

   then transcendence of two perspectives that seem opposite to an

   investigation seriously concerned with the social and political issues

   of the day: the pursuit of a project based on personal experience

   through lonely, isolated investigation and then transcending both

   limitations. It is only by starting from personal experience that one

   could see deeply, could motivate all energies for the pursuit of a

   problem, and eventually see and analyze from the inside those problems

   that are also bothering others; and only through lonely, isolated work

   can one find a way to formulate and deal with these problems properly.

   

   The task of an intellectual (in the Foucaldian and Patockian sense of

   Spirituality) is to drive this line of investigation, personal

   research, the pursuit and formulation of one's own problem, to the

   end.[38] It is only when this task is accomplished that political

   action becomes possible. One must be persevering and patient. The

   trajectories of Foucault and Patocka provide crucial lessons in this

   regard.

   

   Patocka relentlessly pursued his project; therefore, by the time open

   public action against the communist regime became possible, he had

   finished his work and was ready to act. Through this, he left a

   crucial legacy. Foucault, however, got lost in mid-life. In the

   mid-1960s, he got carried away on the wave of structuralism,

   anticipating the fashion and meeting early public success. He soon

   realized his error but compensated for it with an even bigger mistake:

   by a singular decision, he gave up personal work and became active in

   politics, something he had never done before, without finishing his

   task and, therefore, was forced to rely on excessive rhetoric. He got

   out of the mess he created for himself only in the last years of his

   life and only with considerable difficulty. But the earlier impatience

   seriously jeopardized the work, both in terms of its completion and

   its public reception. It is not accidental that for years he did not

   publish under his own name.[39] But, in spite of all he has done

   before and after, his work is judged even today by friend and foe

   alike on the basis of the most questionable aspects of his works

   produced in the mid-1970s.

   

                                   Notes:

                                      

   * This paper revises the Stein Rokkan Lecture, University of Bergen,

          October 1993. I am grateful to members of the Roundtable on

          Political Economy (Northwestern University. Meredith

          Woo-Cumings, director). the International History Workshop

          (University of Chicago, Bruce Cumings, director), and the

          Bergen audience (Stein Kuhnle, chair) for reactions to earlier

          drafts. to John Wiersma for pointing out the similarity of my

          conception of time to that of Norbert Elias. to John Lynn for

          spirited dissent and permission to draw on unpublished

          material, to Ron Aminzade for line-by-line criticism. and to

          Viviana Zelizer for advice on form and content.

          

   1 For a bibliography of Foucault's work, see Bernauer and Rasmussen

          (1988). Concerning the range of his influence, see, for

          example, the special issue of Critique (1986); Megill (1987);

          and the three recent biographies by Eribon (1991), Macey

          (1993), and Miller (1993). Concerning the 1970s, see Foucault

          (1977, 1978a).

          

   2 See especially the three different versions of the Preface or the

          Introduction prepared for the oncoming volume of the History of

          Sexuality project. See Foucault (1988g, 1984, 1986).

          

   3 This is true especially after the study of Taylor (1989).

          

   4 See the debate between Taylor and Connolly: Taylor (1984), Connolly

          (1985), Taylor (1985). See also Connolly (1993).

          

   5 See especially the 1980 and 1982 courses delivered at the College de

          France and also a series of 1981 lectures at Louvain. The

          recently published, carefully edited Dartmouth lectures are

          also important in this respect; see Foucault (1993).

          

   6 See Rabinow (1984), Gordon (1987), Pasquino (1986) concerning Weber,

          and van Krieken (1990).

          

   7 In his excellent study on Patocka and dissident politics, Vaclav

          Belohradsky, a former student of Patocka, discusses Foucault's

          work, but this only refers to the period of the mid-1970s. See

          Belohradsky (1981).

          

   8 It was not possible to trace an English language reference to

          Patocka's in the SSCI. For the scarce English translations, see

          especially Kohak (1989) and also Patocka (1977, Chapter 6 of

          Heretical Essays) and Skilling and Precan (1981).

          

   9 Havel's famous essay "The Power of the Powerless" was dedicated to

          Patocka as was Skillings book (1981), the standard accoount on

          the early history of Czech dissidence.

          

   10 The only other thinker who would deserve it is Bela Hamvas. But as

          publication of his work started in Hungary only in the

          mid-1980s and some of his most important writings are still in

          manuscript, it is not surprising that he is less known abroad,

          though his works are about to appear in Italian and French.

          

   11 For biographical references, see "Jan Patocka: A Philosophical

          Biography" in Kohak (1989), Skilling (1981, pp. 128-31) and

          (1989, pp. 20-3, 235-44), and Patocka (1981, pp. 163-83). As I

          do not read Czech, I had no access to part of the literature.

          

   12 This says much about the idea that "really" East-Central Europe was

          at the heart of Europe at that time.

          

   13 See Kohak (1989, pp. 175-206). The intended table of contents is of

          particular interest for the purposes of this paper: 1. Negative

          Platonism: The Concept of Freedom with Respect to What Exists,

          2. The Problem of Truth, 3. The Problem of the Subject, 4. The

          Suppression of Ontological Dualism, 5. Inanimate Nature and

          Life, 6. Anthropology, 7. History, 8. Constructions of History.

          

   14 Because abroad he started with Husserl and Heidegger, he was

          classified for a long time as a mere commentator.

          

   15 According to several accounts, he had in this way a singular role

          in starting the whole samizdat movement.

          

   16 See Patocka, 1989c, pp. 327-39. About the context of the lecture,

          see also pp. 114-6.

          

   17 See Foucault, 1973, xiv.

          

   18 There seems to be no reference to Patocka whatsoever in the

          literature on Foucault; while, though not mentioning Foucault

          by name, Marc Richir's Preface to a collection of essays by

          Patocka (1988) makes some evident hidden remarks against

          Foucault.

          

   19 About this, see Foucault (1988a, p. 98): Question: "Because behind

          Histoire de la folie lay the problem of Eastern Europe."

          

   Foucault: "Of course. I finished writing that book in Poland and I

          could not fail to think, as I was writing, of what I could see

          around me."

          

   20 Concerning Patocka, see especially the first two of the Heretical

          Essays. Concerning Foucault, see Foucault, 1988c, pp. 12-3, but

          especially the fifth lecture of the 1982 course (February 3,

          1982, C 65 [5]) in which, in answer to a question, Foucault

          claimed that there were two possible ways of studying the links

          between subjectivity and truth, either by using Lacan or

          Heidegger, and he chose the latter.

          

   21 It is to be noted that both are widely acknowledged as crucial

          texts, even if the ideas are enveloped in a commentary (Patocka

          discusses Masaryk, while Foucault a book by Jean

          Daniel--perhaps because neither of them were able or willing to

          formulate directly such a personal statement about the guiding

          force of their work).

          

   22 See Patocka, 1985, p. 137, and see also his ideas about the

          experience of front in Patocka, 1977, pp. 119 ff. The best

          confirmations of Patocka's thesis seem to be the philosophies

          of Hamvas and Wittgenstein, though these are not mentioned by

          him. On the Foucaldian concept of "limit experience," see

          especially the essay "What is Enlightenment" in The Foucault

          Reader, 1984 as well as the long discussion in Miller, 1993,

          though it has a preconceived focus.

          

   23 For Patocka, see especially the Heretical Essays. For Foucault, see

          1988n and the `Introduction' to the Use of Pleasure. The

          concept of "problematisation" was used later by translators of

          Patocka; see, for example, Patocka, 1990a.

          

   24 This was first stated on the first lecture of 1981--the first

          course since 1075 in which the topic discussed was identical

          with the projected title--and never questioned later. See the

          lecture of January 6, 1981, Foucault Archives, C 63 (1).

          

   25 See the fifth lecture of 1084, February 29, 1984, Foucault

          Archives, C 69 (05).

          

   26 They both had the honor of being called Socratic figures, a

          description that could not be applied to many contemporaries.

          (This happened--only?--with Elias and Hamvas.)

          

   27 See Abrams, 1990, p. 5.

          

   28 This is almost identical at all points with the views of Hamvas.

          

   29 See, for example, Eribon, 1991, p. 319.

          

   30 See, for example, Patocka, 1983, p. 87 and Foucault, 1989, p. 145.

          

   31 See Foucault Archives, casette C 65 (1). For related publications,

          see Foucault, 1988c, the outline of the 1982 course in

          Foucault, 1989, and Foucault, 1988d, pp. 44-68, a publication

          based on incomplete student notes.

          

   32 The skeleton of this analysis, taking up a good two hours of

          lectures, is given in four paragraphs in Technologies of the

          Self; see p. 25.

          

   33 About this, see also Flynn, 1988, a useful but very short account

          of this course.

          

   34 It should be emphasized that no similar claim has ever been made by

          Foucault previously, while here it was done at the focal point

          of his most important and explicitly conclusive course.

          

   35 This is especially true for the Weber reconstructed recently by

          Tenbruck and Hennis (Tenbruck, 1980; Hennis, 1988).

          

   36 Patocka read The Order of Things and wrote a review in 1967 but was

          evidently not acquainted with the whole work. Foucault studied

          Patocka in depth in the last year of his life but probably not

          before.

          

   37 For Patocka, see Kohak's Introduction, 1989. Concerning Foucault,

          see, for example, Foucault, 1988e, p. 156: "Whenever I have

          tried to carry out a piece of theoretical work, it has been on

          the basis of my own experience, always in relation to processes

          I saw taking place around me. . . . [his work is] a few

          fragments of Autobiography." See also Foucault, 1988c, p. 11:

          "Each of my works is a part of my own biography. For one or

          another reason I had the occasion to feel and live those

          things." The point, of course, is that this personal research

          is complemented by a passionate interest in the present and

          with ascesis.

          

   38 A reinterpretation of the term "spirituality" is another common

          point between the two thinkers. For Patocka, apart from the two

          major books, see especially Patocka, 1990b. For Foucault, see

          the first lecture of 1982, January 6, 1982 (Foucault Archives,

          C 65 [1]).

          

   39 After the period of the article "Pour un morale de l'inconfort"

          (April-May 1979) that often reads as an intellectual testament,

          Foucault fails to publish anything in his name for two years up

          to an interview given in May 1981 (this is the "Practicing

          Criticism" interview given to Eribon, first defining his work

          as autobiographical). In this period, however, publications

          appear in which Foucault remains anonymous. See Foucault,

          1979b, Foucault, 1988f, pp. 323-30, and also the story told by

          Guibert about Foucault submitting an anonymous article on

          criticism but failing to get it published due to the peculiar

          pseudonyn chosen (Guibert, 1990, pp. 26-7).

          

                               Bibliography:

                                      

   Abrams, Erika, "Avertissement," in Patocka, Jan, Liberti et sacrifice

   (Grenoble: Millon, 1990).

   

   Alford, Fred C., The Self in Social Theory (New Haven, CT: Yale

   University Press, 1991).

   

   Belohradsky, Vaclav, Il mondo della vita: un problema politico

   (Milano: Jaca Book, 1981).

   

   Bernauer, James and Rasmussen, David, eds., The Final Foucault

   (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1988).

   

   Connolly, William, "Taylor, Foucault, and Otherness," in Political

   Theory 13:3 (1985): 365-76.

   

   Connolly, William, "Beyond Good and Evil: The Ethical Sensibility of

   Michel Foucault," in Political Theory 21:3 (1993): 365-89.

   

   Eribon, Didier, Michel Foucault (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University

   Press, 1991).

   

   Flynn, Thomas, "Foucault as Parrhesiast," in Bernauer, James and

   Rasmussen, David, eds., The Final Foucault (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,

   1988).

   

   Foucault, Michel, The Order of Things (New York: Vintage, 1973).

   

   Foucault, Michel, Discipline and Punish (New York: Vintage, 1977).

   

   Foucault, Michel, The History of Sexuality, vol 1. (New York: Vintage,

   1978a).

   

   Foucault, Michel, "Introduction" in Canguilhem, Georges, On the Normal

   and the Pathological (Boston: Reidel, 1978b).

   

   Foucault, Michel, "Pour une morale de l'inconfort," Nouvel Observateur

   (April 23, 1979a).

   

   Foucault, Michel (as Louis Appert), "Luttes autour de prison," in

   Esprit 35 (1979b): 102-111.

   

   Foucault, Michel, `Intended Preface' to History of Sexuality in

   Rabinow, Paul, ed., The Foucault Reader (New York: Pantheon, 1984)

   

   Foucault, Michel, `Introduction' to Use of Pleasure (New York:

   Vintage, 1986).

   

   Foucault, Michel, "On Power," in Kritzman, Lawrence D., ed., Politics,

   Philosophy, Culture (Routledge: London, 1988a).

   

   Foucault, Michel, "The Return of Morality," in Kritzman, Lawrence D.,

   ed., Politics, Philosophy, Culture (Routledge: London, 1988b).

   

   Foucault, Michel, "Truth, Power, Self" in Martin, Luther H., Gutman,

   Huck, and Hutton, Patrick H., Technologies of the Self (London,

   Tavistock, 1988c).

   

   Foucault, Michel, "Hermeneutique du sujet," in Concordia 12 (1988d).

   

   Foucault, Michel, "Practicing Criticism," in Kritzman, Lawrence D.,

   ed., Politics, Philosophy, Culture (Routledge: London, 1988e).

   

   Foucault, Michel, "The Masked Philosopher," in Kritzman, Lawrence D.,

   ed., Politics, Philosophy, Culture (Routledge: London, 1988f).

   

   Foucault, Michel `(Auto)biography', in History of the Present (1988g),

   no. 4.

   

   Foucault, Michel, "The Concern for Truth," in Kritzman, Lawrence D.,

   ed., Politics, Philosphy, Culture (Routledge: London, 1988h).

   

   Foucault, Michel, Resume du cours 1970-1982 (Paris: Juillard, 1989).

   

   Foucault, Michel, "About the Beginning of the Hermeneutics of the

   Self: Two lectures at Dartmouth," Political Theory 21:2 (1993):

   198-227.

   

   Gordon, Colin, "The Soul of the Citizen: Max Weber and Michel Foucault

   on Rationality and Government," in Lash, Scott and Whimster, Sam,

   eds., Max Weber, Rationality and Modernity (London: Allen, 1987).

   

   Guibert, Herve, A l'ami qui ne m'a pas sauve la vie (Paris, Gallimard,

   1990).

   

   Hennis, Wilhelm, Max Weber: Essays in Reconstruction (London: Allen &

   Unwin, 1988).

   

   Kohak, Erazim, ed., Jan Patocka: Philosophy and Selected Writings

   (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989).

   

   Macey, David, The Lives of Michel Foucault (London: Hutchison, 1993).

   

   Megill, Alan, "The Reception of Foucault by Historians," Journal of

   the History of Ideas 48:1 (1987): 117-41.

   

   "Michel Foucault: du monde entier," Critique 471-2 (1986).

   

   Miller, James, The Passion of Michel Foucault (New York: Simon and

   Schuster, 1993).

   

   Pasquino, Pasquale, "Michel Foucault (1926-1984): The will to

   knowledge," Economy and Society 15:1 (1986): 96-109.

   

   Patocka, Jan, "wars of the Twentieth Century and the Twentieth Century

   as War," Telos 30 (1977): 116-26.

   

   Patocka, Jan, Essais heretiques sur la philosophie de l'histoire

   (Paris: Verdier, 1981a).

   

   Patocka, Jan, "Sulla filosofia e i filosofi" (an interview with

   Patocka), in Saggi eretici sulla filosofia della storia (Milan: CSEO,

   1981b).

   

   Patocka, Jan, Platon et l'Europe (Paris: Verdier, 1983).

   

   Patocka, Jan, La crise du sens, I (Brussels, Ousia, 1985).

   

   Patocka, Jan, "Le subjectivisme de la phenomenologie husserlienne et

   la possibilite d'une phenomenologie `asubjective'," in Richir, Marc,

   ed., Qu' est-ce que la phenomenologie? (Grenoble: Millon, 1988).

   

   Patocka, Jan, "Edmund Husserl's Philosophy of the Crisis of the

   Sciences and His Conception of a Phenomenology of the 'Life-World," in

   Kohak, Erazim, ed., Jan Patocka: Philosophy and Selected Writings

   (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989a).

   

   Patocka, Jan, "Cartesianism and Phenomenology," in Kohak, Erazim, ed.,

   Jan Patocka: Philosophy and Selected Writings (Chicago: University of

   Chicago Press, 1989b).

   

   Patocka, Jan, "The Dangers of Technicization in Science according to

   E. Husserl and the Essence of Technology as Danger according to M.

   Heidegger," in Kohyak, Erazin, ed., Jan Patocka: Philosophy and

   Selected Writings (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989c).

   

   Patocka, Jan, `L'homme spirituel et l'intellectuel', in Liberte et

   sacrifice (Grenoble: Millon, 1990a).

   

   Patocka, Jan, "Les fondements spirituels de la vie contemporaine," in

   Liberte et sacrifice (Grenoble: Millon, 1990b).

   

   Patocka, Jan, "L'idee de la culture et son actualite aujourd'hui," in

   L'idee de l'Europe en Boheme (Grenoble: Millon, 1991).

   

   Rabinow, Paul, "Introduction," in Rabinow, Paul, ed., The Foucault

   Reader (New York: Pantheon, 1984).

   

   Skilling, H. Gordon, Charter 77 and Human Rights in Czechoslovakia

   (London: Allen, 1981).

   

   Skilling, H. Gordon, Samizdat and an Independent Society in Central

   and Eastern Europe (London: Macmillan, 1989).

   

   Skilling, H. Gordon and Precan, Vilem, eds., Parallel Politics: Essays

   from Czech and Slovak Samizdat, special issue of International Journal

   of Politics 11:1 (1981): 10-15.

   

   Taylor, Charles, "Foucault on Freedom and Truth," in Political Theory

   12:2 (1984): 152-83.

   

   Taylor, Charles, "Connolly, Foucault, and Truth," in Political Theory

   13:3 (1985): 377-85.

   

   Taylor, Charles, Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern

   Identity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989).

   

   Tenbruck, Friedrich H., "The problem of thematic unity in the works of

   Max Weber," British Journal of Sociology 31:3 (1980): 316-351.

   

   van Krieken, Robert, "The organization of the soul: Elias and Foucault

   on discipline and the self," in Archives Europeennes de Sociologie

   31:2 (1990): 353-71.

   

   Warren, Mark, "Democratic Theory and Self-Transformation," American

   Political Science Review 86: (1992): 8-23

   

   Warren, Mark, "Can Participatory Democracy Produce Better Selves?"

   Political Psychology 14:2 (1993): 209-34.

   

   ~~~~~~~~

   

   By ARPAD SZAKOLCZAI

                             _________________

   

   Copyright of Social Research is the property of New School for Social

   Research and its content may not be copied or emailed to multiple

   sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express

   written permission. However, users may print, download, or email

   articles for individual use.

   Source: Social Research, Summer94, Vol. 61 Issue 2, p297, 27p.

   Item Number: 9410115869

   

Link to Foucault Page
Kindly click here to return to Foucault Page

Kindly click here to return to Academic Interests
Please click here to return to Additional Information

page last updated 28 October 2004
Copyright © 2004 Miguel B. Llora, MA. All Rights Reserved.
Best viewed on Internet Explorer 5.x or later at a minimum of 1024 x 768 resolution