Magazine: American Behavioral Scientist, JUNE-JULY 1995 Record: 1 95080101230002764219950601 Title: The politics of critical description. Subject(s): POWER (Philosophy); FOUCAULT, Michel -- Criticism & interpretation; KNOWLEDGE, Theory of Source: American Behavioral Scientist, Jun/Jul95, Vol. 38 Issue 7, p1018, 24p Author(s): Pels, Dick Abstract: Analyzes the implications of Michael Foucault's genealogy of power and knowledge to delineate a conception of knowledge politics. Confounding of the idea of circular alliance between knowledge and power; Characteristics of the projected relativistic circle; Implications of circular logic of interpretation to critical presentism. AN: 9508010123 ISSN: 0002-7642 Full Text Word Count: 11973 Database: Academic Search Elite THE POLITICS OF CRITICAL DESCRIPTION Recovering the Normative Complexity of Foucault's pouvoir/savoir The slogan that scientific knowledge is a form of politics "continued by other means" harbors an intuition that, despite its disrespectful content, can already pride itself upon a respectable intellectual heritage. In our century, strong traditions of political correctness, of both left-wing and right-wing origin, have dedicated themselves to the demasque of avowedly disinterested products of science as ever so many instances of a bourgeois, antinational, patriarchal, or racist knowledge politics, and have engaged in drives to repoliticize science from the standpoint of the "proletariat," "the people," "the race," or various other allegedly exploited and excluded groups. Resistance against such political rectification, as soon as it moved beyond classical defenses of the value-free nature of science, has in turn sought appeal to a "politics of science" or a politics of rationality. Gouldner's "politics of the mind" was an ambiguous attempt to play in both registers at once and to defend science against politics by political means (Gouldner, 1973, p. 82ff). Bourdieu has placed a rather similar bet in advancing his less rationalistic, more interest-committed notion of a "Realpolitik of Reason" (Bourdieu, 1989, 1991; Pels, 1995). In recent decades, this idea of knowledge politics has acquired a distinctly more radical profile, while the analytical focus has also been redirected more intensely from the external liaisons toward the internal workings of science. As early as Marx and Nietzsche, and certainly since Mannheim's work, the sociology and psychology of knowledge have of course been attentive to quasi-political drives and mechanisms governing the production of knowledge and science. Only recently, however, programmatic research has been building up that focuses on the myriad ways in which scientific claims themselves become power-charged and turn into the prize of intrascientific straggles. One example is provided by critical reassessments of the "politics of theory" which has been invested in the demarcation work of the Durkheimian school in sociology (Lacroix, 1981; Lukes, 1982; Pels, 1983). Other instances are provided by the philosophical critique of Enlightenment rationalism as conducted by Foucault, Derrida, Lyotard, Rorty, and others; by Bourdieu's agonistic field theory of science; and by the epistemological writings of feminists such as Fox Keller, Harding, and Haraway. Not least, the political metaphor has made solid conquests in the constructivist social studies of science as practiced by Bloor, Collins, Knorr, Woolgar, Callon, and Latour. It is here that the Clausewitzean dictum most pointedly sustains a strict refusal to disengage cognitive content and social context, and a determined effort to grasp the shape and operation of those "other means" with which science-as-politics is supposedly continued (e.g., Callon, Law, & Rip, 1986; Latour, 1983, 1987). It is hard to pinpoint with exactitude to what extent this new analytical radicalism has been inspired by Michel Foucault's genealogy of power/ knowledge, as he has developed it from the early 1970s to his early death in 1984. Many of the radical approaches, to be sure, acknowledge the diffuse but deep-reaching impact of his writings (e.g., Latour, 1991; Law, 1986; Rouse, 1987; Shapin, 1994). Notwithstanding such wide repercussions, however, Foucault's grounding intuition about the irreducible mutual implication of power and knowledge continues to pose a delicate epistemological riddle, which, in one commentator's words, has often functioned "as a kind of phantasmatic blank space, to be filled in with the hopes and desires of the interpreter" (Keenan, 1987, p. 12). An impressive phalanx of critics has meanwhile dismissed it as a "performative contradiction" (Habermas, 1987), a "vicious circle" (Cohen & Arato, 1992), as "normatively confused" (Fraser, 1989), and as "paradoxical and ultimately incoherent" (Taylor, 1985, 1986). An equally impressive line of supporters have countered such contestations by foregrounding the critical energy and ethical sensibility of Foucault's genealogical project (e.g., Bernstein, 1994; Connolly, 1985, 1993; Dreyfus and Rabinow, 1982, 1986; Rajchman, 1985). What then to make of the "difficult dash" (Keenan, 1987) that joins and separates knowing and doing, cognition and force, truth and power? My present attempt to reconstruct this intrigue departs from an awareness that Foucault's inconsistencies and contradictions, as publicized in recent debates, cannot satisfactorily be resolved without distancing oneself from some of his formulations, whereas on other points of contention he should be kept more strictly at his word. While departing from Foucault, I will hence also turn (back) against him; and contrary to the commodious prejudice that elevates a lack of system into a principal virtue of Foucaldian style, I will work my way toward a plausibly harmonious and rounded interpretation. Far from claiming to present an hermetic solution to the power/knowledge riddle, however, my aim is to propose a tolerably consistent way of handling or using Foucault, which may be helpful in delineating a more robust and empirically fruitful conception of "knowledge politics." Such streamlining will become especially apparent where I will reinterpret the genealogical intuition in an "irreductionist" and "minimally normative" direction, in order to transcend the classical divorce between facts and values, and to suggest a normative complexity in the analysis of knowledge and power which acknowledges the closeness, rather than the distance, between their "good" and "evil" aspects. FROM DUALISM TO DUALITY Like all principles that make a difference, Foucault's principle of pouvoir/ savoir, or of the indissoluble entanglement of knowledge and power, harbors both a destructive and a constructive impulse. First, it polemicizes against the venerable philosophical tradition extending all the way from the "great Platonic divorce" between truth and power to modern "humanism," which deploys both concepts as quintessential antipodes (Foucault, 1972, pp. 218, 232; 1980, pp. 51-52). Second, it counteracts an equally venerable tradition in political and juridical philosophy, which preferably connotates the exercise of power with repression, exclusion, submission, and censure. Put more constructively, Foucault's pouvoir/savoir reconfigures the semantic field by offering a new definition of knowledge and a new definition of power. The idea of their intrinsic, constitutive, or circular coalition initiates a dual conception of knowledge that emphatically incorporates the inner ambiguities and dark underside of rationality. Simultaneously, by highlighting its productive next to its repressive functioning, a similar duality is installed in the conception of power. These two great Nietzschean themes of the repressive face of reason and the productive face of (the will to) power immediately presuppose and condition one another. It is precisely this epistemological double play that has so far received insufficient notice in the extensive literature that has been triggered by Foucault's work. It is profitable, however, to consider them as a conceptual couple that should be more intimately "thought together." Because the desublimation of reason moves in step with a rehabilitation of the traditional conception of power, their former hierarchical antinomy is absorbed in a new epistemological and normative equilibrium. Truth and power (its traditional "other") acquire comparable, if not equal philosophical status and are much more closely intertwined. Although (the quest for) truth reveals an intrinsic impurity, and is "downgraded" through the direct complicity with its traditional dark side, (the will to) power rises in epistemological prestige once it acquires cardinal functions in the production of truth, reality, and desire. This simultaneous "evening out" of the epistemological balance and contraction of the previous polarity work toward the same end: duality. Duality refers to the tempering of the normative energies of an established conceptual asymmetry in a generative coalition that yields a new, and weaker, principle of discrimination (Pels, 1987, 1990, 1993). While the traditionally positive becomes less positive, the traditionally negative also becomes less negative; positivity and negativity are resettled in much closer vicinity, without losing their normative tension. One of the most intriguing features of the Foucaldian principle of pouvoir/savoir is perhaps that precisely by breaking the dominant binary code and melting knowledge and power into such a close coalition, the productive and repressive dimensions of both power and knowledge are now considered mutually constitutive rather than antithetical. This is enough to instill in both concepts a radical epistemological and ethical complexity. It is not hard to reap citations in order to illustrate this equilibrating double play. In his 1970 inaugural lecture, Foucault precisely articulates the dangerous and violent character of speech and suggests that the order of discourse is characteristically constituted by miscellaneous procedures of exclusion, rarefaction, and misrecognition, which simultaneously exorcise and occlude these intrinsic powers and dangers. What appears before our eyes "is only the truth of wealth, fertility, and sweet strength in all its insidious universality. In contrast, we are unaware of the prodigious machinery of the will to truth, with its vocation of exclusion" (Foucault, 1972, p. 220). Knowledge can no longer be conceived in terms of a neutral, disinterested reflection of objective reality. Interpretation equals conquest: Instead of uncovering objective meanings, interpretation is "the violent or surreptitious appropriation of a system of rules, which in itself has no essential meaning." A reflexive, genealogical self-questioning of the work of historical interpretation reveals that historical consciousness is not free from passion or interest, but harbors an impassioned "will to truth." That is to say that "all knowledge rests upon injustice (that there is no right, not even in the act of knowing, to truth or a foundation for truth) and that the instinct for knowledge is malicious." (Foucault, 1977b, pp. 151, 163). Discourse must be conceived as "a violence that we do to things, or, at all events, as a practice which we impose upon them" (Foucault, 1972, p. 229). If truth is presently "a thing of this world" (Foucault, 1980, p. 131) and has become something prosaic and commonplace, the traditional mundanity of power in turn becomes less dirty and subterranean. Foucault's criticism of transcendental views of rationality is complemented by the idea that power interests exercise a productive, perspective-constituting function in the formation of knowledge. Rather than continuing the negative vocabulary of censorship, prohibition, and distortion, we should recognize that "power produces; it produces reality; it produces domains of objects and rituals of truth" (Foucault, 1977a, p. 194). What maintains power and makes it acceptable is the fact that it does not only weigh on us as a nay-saying force, "but that it traverses and produces things, it induces pleasure, forms knowledge, produces discourse" (Foucault, 1980, p. 199). The lapidary statement that "far from preventing knowledge, power produces it" (p. 59) may then be read as a rudimentary "flashlight theory" of power, according to which objects of knowledge are rendered accessible only because they are delineated and illuminated by power drives and practices (Visker, 1990, p. 71). It is arguable, however, that Foucault envisages something more radical than such a "perspectivism of power," by suggesting a theory of constitution according to which reality is performatively made rather than merely "encountered" in its multifarious disorder. In this constructivism of power, both reality and the knowledge of it are produced in the course of and by means of the practical "violence that we do to things." At once I like to counter a double misapprehension to which Foucault's own formulations give rise, but which is also triggered by reflexes of the axiomatic split between knowledge and power, which he attempts to subvert. This misunderstanding is fostered by a twofold reductionism. The grounding rule that "truth isn't outside of power, or lacking in power" is routinely interpreted in terms of a desire to reduce knowledge, truth, and science to power practices, which ultimately stages power as a transcendental demiurge or an ontological a priori that is taken to be constitutive of all "true speaking." Likewise, Foucault is suspected of an urge to replace the repressive or juridical conception of power by its productive or disciplinary counterpart. In both dimensions, he would supposedly be concerned to effect a critical inversion of established models of the relationship between knowledge and power and of the negative and positive modalities of power exercise, without actually superseding the dualistic framework itself. It must be conceded that such misunderstandings are actively enhanced by Foucault's intermittent tendency to reify notions of power, domination, and discipline, and to assign them a transcendentally constitutive function (e.g., Foucault, 1977a, p. 193; 1977b, pp. 150-151; 1978, pp. 158-159; 1980, pp. 59, 93; 1988a, p. 118). In various contexts, he also appears to lend epistemological primacy to the productive over the repressive theory of power (e.g., Foucault, 1978, pp. 73, 85-86; 1980, pp. 59, 119), whereas other passages, such as the one cited above, place all emphasis upon the "malicious" rather than the productive nature of the "will to know." In other words, Foucault's genealogies regularly flirt with a critical methodology of renversement or inversion (Foucault, 1972, pp. 229, 231; cf. Rajchman, 1985, p. 56). Criticisms such as those offered by Habermas (1987), Dews (1987), Cohen and Arato (1992), or McCarthy (1994) of the essentialist or ontological quality of Foucault's concept of power are therefore definitely on target. However, there are also reasons to suppose that Foucault intends to escape from this reductionist drift and is groping toward "irreductionist" principles, which equally discard the dualism of knowledge and power as that of repressive versus productive (knowledge) power. Foucault sometimes bends the stick in the other direction, but is also chased by the residual logic of both traditional oppositions. Still, it is much more interesting to interpret the "circular" coincidence of knowledge and power and that of production and repression as an attempt to leap twice from dualism to duality.[1] In both cases, this leap departs from the magnetic poles to the middle reaches of the force field, reallocating properties that were hitherto defined by the oppositional dualism. With Dreyfus and Rabinow, I consider this view of the "simultaneity" of knowledge and power, where neither can be explained in terms of or can be reduced to the other, as constituting the most radical dimension of Foucault's work (Dreyfus & Rabinow, 1982, pp. 114, 194, 203; cf. Keenan, 1987, pp. 14-15).[2] Illumination of the seamy side of rationality does as little to replace the traditional panegyric of reason as does illumination of power's positivity substitute for the idea of negative power. In his inaugural lecture, Foucault (1972) already unravels the intrinsic link between the ordering of the world by truthful discourses and the exclusion and rarefaction that they inevitably bring in their train (cf. Visker, 1990, pp. 128-129). The will to know is simultaneously part of the danger and a tool to combat that danger (Rabinow, 1984, p. 7). In an interview from 1983, this inner ambiguity of reason is signaled in the following terms: "If intellectuals in general are to have a function, if critical thought itself has a function . . . it is precisely to accept this sort of spiral, this sort of revolving door of rationality that refers us to its necessity, to its indispensability, and at the same time, to its intrinsic dangers" (Foucault, 1984a, p. 249). A similar spiraling connection between "indispensability" and "danger" can be situated in the concept of power. In Gordon's interpretation, the novelty of Foucault's approach is that he locates thinking about power "beyond good and evil," that is, outside the force field that extends between a positively benign sociological model of power as the agency of social cohesion and normality and a more polemical representation of power as an instance of repression, violence, and coercion. In doing so, Foucault (1980, pp. 234-235) introduces a methodological principle of neutrality or skepticism in the analysis of power. It is not clear, however, in what sense neutrality and skepticism precisely cohere. In my view, Foucaldian skepticism is not exhausted by the neutralization of the dualism of enabling and constraining power but carries a much wider significance, whereas also the interconnection between productive and repressive power should be conceived in a more intrinsic or constitutive fashion. The revolving door of power is not only similar in shape to the revolving door of rationality: It is one and the same door.[3] That is to suggest that the principle of pouvoir/savoir, while indeed passing beyond established distributions of good and evil, does so in a very specific sense that does not signify an adieu to all normative deliberation in favor of dispassionate scientific description. Foucault's analysis is only neutral and agnostic in terms of the classical dualisms that he singles out for attack, and does not per se include a plea for normative neutrality or value-free naturalism. Skeptical awareness of the paradoxal proximity between rationality and irrationality and between productive and restrictive power, which results from bracketing their unmixed antithesis, does not entail the bracketing of all forms of ethical sensibility and purpose. Rather, it suggests a novel minimal normativity according to which good and evil no longer constitute transcendental antipodes but live together much more closely than is accounted for in conventional ethical discourse. If light and dark sides to some extent condition one another, positive and negative dimensions are deployed much more ambiguously than either a traditional sociological functionalism or a traditional ethics will find palatable. I believe that the fundamental skepticism that exudes from such an awareness of circular connections between good and evil stands close to the heart of Foucault's philosophical ethos (Connolly, 1993; Rabinow, 1984, p. 47; Rajchman, 1985; Rochlitz, 1992).[4] This talk of good and evil, to be sure, reinforces a normative reading of the complexity that is instituted by the duality of the positive and the negative, according to which sociological assessments of indispensability and danger (or production and repression) are to some extent taken as secularized and "scientized" recodings of much older moral antinomies. When explaining that power does not operate through prohibition and negation, but is productive of true speaking, of the sexualizing of bodies or of the normalization of subjectivity, Foucault usually employs a "cool" sociotechnical sense of productivity, which appears to preclude a normative stance with regard to the technologies or disciplines involved. If he insists that power is much more than a negative instance but should be conceived as a productive network that runs through the entire social body, or that productive disciplinary power supplies the necessary basis for the great negative or juridical forms of power, the linkage between positivity and negativity appears to stand closer to the analytical relationship between whole and part than to the normative relationship between good and evil. Nevertheless, I suppose there is interpretive room for a less neutral or technological conception of the duality of enablement/constraint or that of production/repression, both in the case of knowledge and in that of power. In this conception, many apparently secular sociological antinomies (authority vs. power, agency vs. structure, subject vs. object, consensus vs. conflict, normal vs. pathological[5]) retain significant residues of the religious and moral distinction between good and evil and remain laterally connected with its manifold contemporary representations, even though dominant epistemologies actively repress or passively neglect such normative resonances. The theorem about the proximity or duality of the positive and the negative, in this particular sense, does not elevate sociological concepts (such as knowledge and power) to a generic level of abstraction ruled by moral indifference, but opts for a more intricate and demanding interpretation according to which good and evil cohabitate closely enough to put all naturalistic distinctions into epistemological disorder.[6] FACTS AND VALUES Next to filing an analytic claim, the idea of the revolving door of knowledge power thus also carries a normative point. This entails that, in their turn, descriptive and normative judgments are much more tightly ensnared than is acknowledged by standard conceptions in philosophy and social-political theory (Pels, 1990; Root, 1993). Such a claim to interpret the central intuition of pouvoir/savoir in terms of a critical mixture of factual and value statements not only propels us into the storm center of the Foucault debate (cf. Armstrong, 1992; Kelly, 1994), but distances us even more pertinently from the image that Foucault himself has irregularly upheld of the naturalistic methodological import of his genealogical project. However, a "minimally normative" amendment of Foucault appears called for if we wish to cope successfully with some important objections that have been leveled against the "descriptivism" and "crypto-normativism" of his historical analyses. The most incisive and widely publicized critique has of course been raised by Habermas, Foucault's great sparring partner in the philosophical debate about the Enlightenment (Habermas, 1987; cf. also Bernstein, 1994; Cohen & Arato, 1992; Fraser, 1989; Honneth, 1994; Taylor, 1986). While acknowledging the legitimacy of this line of critique, I also presume that a relapse into the dualistic and universalistic (or "humanistic") framework from which Habermas operates can and should be avoided; differently put, that the principle of pouvoir/savoir generates an indigenous normative criterion for a critical theory that does not lay claim to a universally compelling or transcendental type of validation. Foucault's genealogies have often been read (and liberally permit such a reading) as products of an epistemological leap from normative toward straight-forwardly descriptive theory (cf. Habermas, 1987; Taylor, 1986). Normativity is usually interpreted as "normalization" (Cohen & Arato, 1992, p. 296). Habermas has typically claimed that Foucault systematically eludes value judgments and the more general issue of the justification of critique in favor of value-free historical explanations, and thus naturalistically reduces the dimension of "ought" to that of "is." Genealogical historiography, he has argued, confronts the mutually sealed discursive universes, which permit only internal strife about norms and values, and their underlying practices of power in a strictly descriptive, nonparticipatory if not ascetic manner. It brackets normative validity claims as well as claims to propositional truth and elopes the question whether some discourse and power formations can be more legitimate than others. Here Habermas gratefully fastens upon Foucault's own characterization of the genealogical temperament as a "felicitous positivism," and Paul Veyne's depiction of Foucault as the historian "in a pure state," who desires nothing further than stoically to announce "wie es wirklich gewesen ist" (Habermas, 1987, pp. 275-276, 282). Such detachment, however, ensnares Foucault in a major aporia. The cool facade of his radical historicism hardly conceals the critical passions that rage underneath. Foucault's normative engagement is palpable right down to his style and choice of words, but can nowhere be explicitly acknowledged. His reductionist naturalism fosters the same crypto-normativism for which he himself has indicted the supposedly value-free human sciences. The idea that there is something wrong with modern disciplinary knowledge power presupposes the salience of particular normative standards, and such standards are indeed subliminally present in Foucault's genealogies. However, because they are not articulated as such, Foucault falls victim to an "arbitrary partisanship" and an "unholy subjectivism" (Habermas, 1987, pp. 276, 284). Once again, it must be conceded that Foucault makes himself eminently vulnerable to this reproach. The expression "positivisme heureux" from his 1970 inaugural lecture does not fail to conjure up misgivings, whereas the genealogical deconstruction of moral-utopian and juridico-political discourses often exemplifies a strong historicist and positivistic drift (cf. Dews, 1987, p. 180). Against totalizing theories that unveil finalistic continuities of historical development, genealogy intends carefully to "listen to history" (Foucault, 1977b, p. 142) in order to study with minimal prejudice how knowledge power actually functions. Foucault's critique does not say that things are not all right as they are, but is out to show how and why things have become what they are (cf. Visker, 1990, pp. 111-112). The genealogical method performs this critical task primarily by revealing the historical arbitrariness of the present by demonstrating that that-which-is has not always existed but is the product of a patchwork of contingencies (Foucault, 1983, p. 206; 1977b, p. 146; 1990/1994, pp. 74-75). Accordingly, the grounding rule of pouvoir/savoir itself is introduced as an apparently neutral proposition about its factual omnipresence. Consider the following characteristic and by no means isolated statement: The exercise of power perpetually creates knowledge and, conversely, knowledge constantly induces effects of power. . . . Modern humanism is therefore mistaken in drawing this line between knowledge and power. Knowledge and power are integrated with one another, and there is no point in dreaming of a time when knowledge will cease to depend on power; this is just a way of reviving humanism in a utopian guise. It is not possible for power to be exercised without knowledge, it is impossible for knowledge not to engender power (Foucault, 1980, p. 52). Suspicions raised by critics such as Habermas, Fraser, Taylor, or Dews, that such statements represent somewhat more than mere empirical-historical generalizations, certainly appear justified. Foucault's "critical historicism" (Rabinow, 1984) does not simply add critique to historical analysis, but appears to presume a much more immediate and internal relationship between both types of endeavor. From a traditional conception of the logical tie between facts and values, it may indeed seem as if normative considerations are entirely swallowed by empirical generalizations. Even Habermas, who refuses the sharp heterogeneity between the discourses of truth and normativity, without ceasing to assign them to separate domains (cf. Habermas, 1992), cannot react otherwise than by the familiar reflex of reproaching Foucault for sliding into a naturalistic reductionism. It would be more exciting, on the other hand, to inquire whether Foucault, rather than reducing values to facts, pulls off a more intriguing trick that positions him beyond the traditional playground of the logical dualism itself. Foucault's genealogy, if so interpreted, would once again effect a double epistemological leap away from both objective statements of fact and universalistic moral prescriptions in the direction of mixtures of facts and values whose connection is so intimate that the descriptions necessarily bring along their own normativity (and the other way around). Once again, this "natural proximity" of facts and values must be interpreted in an explicitly irreductionist sense (Pels, 1990). That genealogy may be fruitfully seen as a project of "critical" or "evaluative" description (cf. also Bernstein, 1994, p. 227; Kelly, 1994) is borne out by a number of important suggestions. Any diagnosis of the present, Foucault asserts, must manage to grasp "why and how that-which-is might no longer be that-which-is" by following "lines of fragility" in the present; any description must hence always be made in accordance with the possible spaces of freedom, the transformative possibilities that the present offers (Foucault, 1984b, pp. 126-127). The "ironic heroization" of the present, which is characteristic of the ethos of modernity, its "trans figuring play of freedom with reality," intends to transform it "not by destroying it but by grasping it in what it is" --although this must not be taken in the sense that prescriptions are derivable from descriptions (p. 127). Modernity is an exercise "in which extreme attention to what is real is confronted with the practice of a liberty that simultaneously respects this reality and violates it" (p. 41). Even though Foucault remains somewhat enigmatic, his injunction to follow "fractures" or "lines of fragility" in order to discover "spaces of freedom" within the real appears to experiment with an irreductionist notion of the proximity of empirical facts and critical values, which draws both terms much closer together than traditional epistemology will allow.[7] Expressions such as "critical ontology of the present" or "critical ontology of ourselves" (Foucault, 1984b, p. 50) only serve to enhance this impression.[8] Insofar as Foucault still tends to elope an explicit justification of the normative implications of his genealogical reconstructions, he remains vulnerable to critique. But this does not at all imply, as Habermas and other critics demand, that Foucault is obliged to supply transcendentalist foundations for his normative assumptions and that everything that falls below this exacting standard can be written off in terms of "arbitrary partisanship." Neither does it seem correct, as Kunneman is concerned to argue, that such universalistic criteria of justification are implicitly present in Foucault's oeuvre; that its normative groundwork therefore exemplifies strong affinities with that of Habermas's own theory; and that the latter inadequately attends to the (good) reasons that Foucault might offer for renouncing a systematic justification thereof (Kunneman, 1986, p. 367ff). Rather, the most decisive reason for refusing such a justification is that Foucault's critique of propositional truths and prescriptive values precisely intends to undercut such presumptions of universalism; from his perspective, the call for rationalistic foundations is a type of "Enlightenment blackmail" (Foucault, 1984b, pp. 41-42; 1990/1994, p. 118). His own critical project no longer seeks to identify "the universal structures of all knowledge or of all possible moral action" but fully recognizes the local, specific, and contingent nature of critique (Foucault, 1984b, pp. 250, 46; 1988b, p. 11; 1991b, pp. 73-74).[9] Habermas has complained about genealogy's "irritating double play" in claiming for its concept of power the innocence of an empirically based category, while simultaneously deploying it as a grounding concept in a metaphysical theory of constitution (Habermas, 1987, pp. 270, 273-274; cf. also McCarthy, 1994). This transcendental quality, he argues, is precisely what lends the empirical analysis of technologies of power their significance as a critique of rationality, and what secures for genealogical historiography its unmasking effect. Although his intuition about genealogy's double role appears correct, Habermas also appears to miss the very proximity between facts and values that was identified earlier and that both relativizes the claimed "innocence" of empirical inquiry and the metaphysical nature of Foucault's grounding of critique in a transcendental priority of power networks. Foucault's genealogical descriptions get by very well without the pretense toward objectivity, which is supported by functionalist sociology; neither must the synthetic coupling of knowledge and power inevitably be conceived in transcendental and aphoristic terms. The constitutive synthesis of knowledge and power is not ontologically framed -- at least not in the conventional sense (cf. Foucault, 1990/1994, p. 128) -- but assembles constative and normative judgments in a critical mix, which, while renouncing rationalistic strategies of validation, offers a perspective according to which discursive formations and power practices can simultaneously be redescribed and put to the ethical test. This enterprise does as little require an external justification of truth claims as it does pursue an external grounding of its normative assumptions. THE HISTORY OF THE PRESENT In order to see why this is not as paradoxical as Habermas and other rationalists think it is, we may shift toward another corner of the debate, in order to attend to the specific manner in which Foucault's genealogical method mingles and balances "presentist" and "anti-presentist" elements. His attempt to break free from the customary prejudice that only values the past in terms of the here and now, tends to approximate him to a value-free and relativistic historicism that severs the epistemological link with the present in that it undertakes to study the past in its own context and in its own terms. Simultaneously, however, Foucault advocates a critical perspectivism that rebuilds the bridge between present and past in that it explicitly subordinates historical analysis to current interests and problematics. At the close of the first chapter of Discipline and Punish, for example, Foucault (1977a) wonders what is actually at stake in the history that he aspires to write: "Why? Simply because I am interested in the past? No, if one means by that writing a history of the past in terms of the present. Yes, if one means writing the history of the present" (pp. 30-31). This simultaneous yes and no concentrates the dilemma of Foucault's "critical historicism." For how can the modest vocation to "listen to history" be squared with the perspectival "violence" that is committed in historical interpretation? What is the import of the "dedicated boldness" or "studious audacity" that Foucault considers characteristic for the critical style?[10] How can genealogy be conducted as "anti-science" (Foucault, 1980, p. 83)? We may encircle this dilemma a little more closely in Foucault's 1971 programmatic essay on "Nietzsche, Genealogy, History." Here, the genealogical method is primarily articulated in opposition to a finalistic metaphysics, which depicts the development of history in terms of singular continuities and closed totalities (Foucault, 1977b, p. 140). Against the solemnity of this originary metaphysics, which locates the essential identity and all true possibilities of things in their first beginnings, genealogy prefers to "listen to history" in order to uncover differences, deviations, discontinuities, and dispersions. Then it is revealed that these pontifical essences mask something totally different, something vulgar and mundane: Reason, truth, and scientific method draw a veil over chance, passion, and the will to power (pp. 142-145). For Foucault, presentism is equal to the unreflected retrojection of contemporary interests, institutions, and practices that are "lived" as absolute and universalistic ones, and he resists a retrojective historiography that encourages such "subjective recognitions." Knowledge does not depend on rediscovery and emphatically excludes the "rediscovery of ourselves." True historiography does no longer search for the roots of our identity but "introduces discontinuity into our very being" (pp. 152, 154, 162). It is no longer a question "of judging the past in the name of a truth that only we can possess in the present; but risking the destruction of the subject who seeks knowledge in the endless deployment of the will to knowledge" (p. 164).[11] It is highly improbable, therefore, that Foucault endorses a form of historicism that contents itself with stoically detached descriptions of history's capricious game of chance, with a meticulous study of the origins of things that would at most elicit an indirect critique of their ostensibly serene eternality. The genealogical project does not entail a relapse into empiricism or positivism, but envisages an anti-disciplinarian "anti-science," which is geared toward the emancipation of disqualified and illegitimate knowledges and wishes little by little to build up "strategic knowledge" (Foucault, 1980, pp. 83-85, 108, 145). It is anchored in a philosophical ethos according to which "the critique of what we are is at one and the same time the historical analysis of the limits that are imposed on us and an experiment with the possibility of going beyond them" (Foucault, 1984b, p. 50). The fine-grained but crucial difference between a "history in terms of the present" and a "history of the present" does hence not concern the practice of critical reconstruction or retrojection as such, which even Foucault considers inevitable, but the absolutism or "apocalyptic objectivism" that tends to transform this practice into a metaphysics of origin and into finalistic grand narratives. Genealogy does not so much aim at objective analyses of historical structures of meaning or practices "in their own terms," but rather at reconstructive interpretations that issue from a contemporary critical perspective and that bend history to its will just like the grand totalizing narratives, while refusing to commit itself to their totalitarian foundationalist pretenses.[12] Indeed, Foucault does not hesitate to characterize genealogy as perspectival, engaged, and, in this specific sense, "malicious" and "unjust." The impulse to understand everything without hierarchy, without judgment or preference, is nothing but "sanctimonious objectivity," and stands squarely opposed to the Nietzschean conception of reflexivity: Historians take unusual pains to erase the elements in their work which reveal their grounding in a particular time and place, their preferences in a controversy -- the unavoidable obstacles of their passion. Nietzsche's version of historical sense is explicit in its perspective and acknowledges its system of injustice. Its perception is slanted, being a deliberate appraisal, affirmation, or negation; it reaches the lingering and poisonous traces in order to prescribe the best antidote. It is not given to a discrete effacement before the objects it observes and does not submit itself to their processes; nor does it seek laws, since it gives equal weight to its own sight and to its objects. (Foucault, 1977b, pp. 156-157) By virtue of this reflexive historical sense, genealogy is also capable of writing its own genealogy, in terms of a "vertical projection" of its own position (pp. 156-157). In this light it appears puzzling that Habermas both castigates Foucault for his "transcendental historicism" and simultaneously suspects him of an inadvertent presentism. In his view, Foucault wishes merely to deliver a "stoical" analysis of meaningless structures of power, dismissing the idea of a hermeneutic dialogue between the historian and the past. But, as Habermas insists, the explanation of technologies of power is only feasible from a comparative perspective, which in turn presupposes a hermeneutic point of departure that inevitably incorporates a diagnosis of its own time. Foucault is therefore guilty of the same presentism from which he claims to escape, in that he deploys a vertical projection of his own position without the concomitant reflexive consciousness (Habermas, 1987, pp. 276-278). However, as soon as it is recognized that Foucault self-consciously lowers his genealogical sounding lead into the deep waters of history, one can only wonder at this critique. Once again such misunderstandings appear rooted in genealogy's unresolved tensions between positivistic historicism and critical perspectivism. In my judgment, such tensions are largely ascribable to the fierceness of Foucault's resistance against the tyranny of globalizing grand narratives, which leads him to identify their universalistic validity claims rather immediately with their quest for an overarching, unifying systematics. Historicization, for Foucault, always channels a double intent: It undercuts allegedly necessary and eternal foundations of truth and morality, while simultaneously uprooting and pulverizing global systems of thought in favor of highlighting discontinuities and differences. Hence "anti-foundationalism" modulates into "difference thinking" without apparent transition. But whereas the unmasking critique of transcendental foundations of truth, morality, and method presupposes a critically presentist point of view, the methodological preference for fragmentation, discontinuity, and dispersal continually pushes toward a renewed severance of this supply line between present and past. I see no principled reason, however, why "differentialism" and its positivistic drift cannot be cut loose from the critique of epistemological foundationalism. The heightened attention to historical fortuities, contingencies, thresholds, and coupures does not forbid the reincorporation of miscellaneous differences into a new narrative of continuity that is not a narrative of origins but is explicitly conceived as a knowledge-political re-construction that departs from a critical position in the present. In the absence of the solid anchorpoints and the granite foundations of tall stories, it remains perfectly possible to tell small stories that group differences and details into a consistent narrative line. IN THE CRITICAL CIRCLE Small stories are not essentialist myths of origin but knowledge-political retrojections that are launched from an unstable, "uncertified" standpoint in the present. Because they depart from the present and orbit back through a histo-riographic detour to their point of departure, they are ensnared in a hermeneutic circle. Is this circular movement by definition a vicious one? Does the axiom of pouvoir/savoir escape the paradoxal relativism of a principle that inevitably bites its own tail? We may repeat our crucial question: How can the idea of an intrinsic coalition between knowledge and power function critically? Once again it is Habermas who deftly illuminates these problems through the acuity of his formulations. With his radical critique of rationality, it is argued, Foucault entangles himself in a reflexive paradox. Genealogy is concerned to explicate the origins of knowledge naturalistically in terms of practices of power, but this explanatory baseline can be reached only because Foucault ceases to think genealogically as soon as his own historiography comes into view. He is unable to explain the provenance of his own objectivity claims. When truth claims cannot transcend the discourse totalities in which they are embedded, and the latter invariably function as "protuberances" of power complexes, this naturally also holds for Foucault's own discourse. If knowledge cannot break out of the enchanted circle of power, and all counterpower inevitably moves within the horizon of the power that it combats, how then is Foucault able to sustain the superiority of his genealogy? Does it not exhaust itself in a mere "politics of theory" (Habermas, 1987, pp. 247, 268-269, 276-281)?[13] However, this classically toned critique of the alleged performative "self-destruction" of relativism overshoots its mark. The reflexive paradox that Habermas discerns is a projection of his own theoretical preoccupations. "Theory politics" or "the politics of truth," for Foucault, is far from being a dirty word (cf. Foucault, 1980, pp. 132-133; 1990/1994, p. 68): Nowhere does he claim a transcontextual objectivity or seek a transcontextual foundation that negates the principle of knowledge power itself. If the counterdiscourse of genealogy implicitly claims a larger amount of validity than the discourses it resists, this superiority is anyhow not derived from the kind of anticipatory divorce between truth and power, which is still upheld in the Habermasian utopia of the ideal speech situation. The theory of knowledge power includes an immediate reference to its own grounding; but this self-referentiality only "destroys" the validity basis of its own critical analysis if one aprioristically claims a type of validity that pretends to escape with all its might from the context of power.[14] Hence I forward the thesis that the cognitive and normative superiority of Foucaldian genealogy is precisely accountable to its refusal to divorce knowledge and power according to the "humanist" recipe. Rather than abandoning itself to the relativistic destruction of all truth rules, the principle of pouvoir/ savoir circularly establishes its own criterion of legitimacy. This criterion cannot be externally justified or anchored according to the prescriptions of rationalistic epistemology, in that it does not extend beyond the knowledge-political context of the genealogical discourse within which it is raised. This does not issue in a form of agnostic, value-free relativism that views historical formations of discourse and power as closed systems and excludes any and all normative comparison between them. On the contrary: Foucaldian genealogy offers a critically normative vantage point that does not only apply the principle of truth power to other discourses but also to itself, itself offering a calibration point for historical comparison. Consequently, Foucault does not oppose truth to power, but ranges one form of knowledge politics against another (Foucault, 1980, pp. 132-133).[15] The foundationalist concept of truth, which sets power and truth in energetic opposition, is replaced by a new relativizing concept of truth that does no longer separate them. Different from what Cohen and Arato (and many others) presume, critique is not disempowered by an analysis that "equates discourse, reflection, and truth with power strategies," nor is it disqualified by the skeptical insight that successful resistance "merely" substitutes one strategy of power for another (Cohen & Arato, 1992, p. 292). The estimation that even an antiscience such as genealogy and the counterpowers that it musters will inevitably generate new forms of demarcation and exclusion, new elites of knowledge, and new complexes of power is the very opposite of an invitation to cynicism and political apathy (Foucault, in Dreyfus & Rabinow, 1982, pp. 231-232). Rather, it has fully digested the skeptical intuition that resistance against the established disciplinary powers, by the very need to challenge them, cannot but invest in the conflict and is forced to adopt some of the characteristics of its adversary. In this respect as well, the utopian purity of a Manichean struggle between the forces of good and evil, and of the inevitable triumph of the good, is exchanged for an appreciation of their unavoidable proximity. The movement that crusades against the established knowledge powers in order to found a new regime of truth does not offer an exception to this rule.[16] Once again Foucault's formulations are ambiguous, so that consistent interpretation necessarily borders on critical amendation. If he insists that the problem does not consist in how to draw the demarcation line between truth and untruth, but to analyze historically "how effects of truth are produced within discourses which in themselves are neither true nor false" (Foucault, 1980, p. 118; cf. 1990/1994, p. 78), genealogy itself offers an eloquent exception to this agnosticist rule. Likewise, it demarcates between truth and falsity, although not with the help of classical truth rules, which demand sharp distanciation from power interests. The critical description of the mechanisms of disciplinary power (e.g., of "true speaking" as a product of confessional power techniques) supports an alternative conception of truth that recognizes that the power of (traditional) truth claims precisely issues from the misrecognition of their power-infused character. Henceforth all "truths" are rendered suspect that actively deny the social enforcement by which they are constituted. Against the dominant regime of truth, Foucault pleads in favor of a new regime, of new (and weaker) rules of demarcation, of "ascertaining the possibility of a new politics of truth." This does not entail its emancipation from every system of power (which remains a chimerical option) but "of detaching the power of truth from the forms of hegemony, social, economic, and cultural, within which it operates at the present time" (Foucault, 1980, p. 133). In order to trace the path of this critical circle, we may go on to examine Foucault's objection to the reductionist style of traditional ideology critique -- an objection that is widely shared among philosophers and social theorists who are routinely lumped together as postmodernists. Foucault and others find this concept of ideology fundamentally worrisome, because it is consistently erected against supposedly transparent conceptions of truth or reality. The new conception of the intrinsic alliance between truth and power, however, does no longer permit us to think that the world is transparent and immediately accessible to knowledge. Genealogy rejects the naturalistic premise that "under power with its acts of violence and its artifice, we should be able to rediscover the things themselves in their primitive vivacity" (Foucault, 1988b, p. 119). Simultaneously, however, Foucault regularly deploys the concept of ideology in a critical context, and refers to an underlying (?) reality that is being masked, distorted, or concealed (cf. Cohen & Arato, 1992, pp. 262-263; Dews, 1987, pp. 183, 190; Foucault, 1972, pp. 227-228; 1980, pp. 105-108). Which new framework of truth operates as yardstick of judgment? Or differently put: How is an antirealist critique of ideology possible? It is evident from the very outset that such a critique renounces all capacity to unmask the knowledge position of the adversary as "power-infused" or "interest-committed," while excepting one's own position as untainted by such blemishes. The principle of truth power sensitizes to the power orientation of all positions: It shifts the epistemological balance between cognition and social interest and suggests a different assessment of the function of social interests themselves. This leaves only one logical possibility for locating a workable criterion of ideology critique. This criterion can only be posited by the principle of truth power itself, which is then licensed to "unmask" all conceptual positions that are unable or unwilling to respect this very same principle. This turns ideology critique not only into a reflexive but also into a circular enterprise.[17] On the one hand, such critique is capable of "unmasking" all discourses that consider themselves interest-free and conceal their commitment by knowledge-political maneuvering as illusory and different from what they really are. On the other hand, this very reduction of ideas to a context- and power-free factuality is impossible, in that the critique cannot break loose from its own normative point of departure. This is not an impossible paradox. One may continue to thematize the discrepancy between distorted self-image and reality, between what discourses say and what they actually "are" or "do." However, such reality judgments and the attendant imputation of "false consciousness" remain logically dependent upon a critical outsider's perspective, which is established by the principle of truth power itself.[18] Because objects of knowledge are invariably constituted by means of specific patterns of symbolic power, the occultation of "reality" can only be revealed from a knowledge-political perspective that eschews all appeals to an independent reality that transcends the circle. In this manner, the disclosure and the occultation of reality necessarily co-produce one another. AGAINST OBJECTIVISM This circular, strictly contextualist criterion of truth therefore still permits the deployment of a "negative" or critical concept of ideology. Examples of such denunciatory critique are found in the destruction that Madness and Civilization (Foucault, 1965) brings upon the idealistic, positivistic self-image of psychology (cf. Visker, 1990, pp. 27-28) or in the analogous demasque, in The History of Sexuality I, of sex as a correlate and product of the discursive practice of the scientia sexualis (Foucault, 1978, pp. 67-70). The principle of this critical analysis is generalized in Foucault's inaugural lecture, where the "sly" nature of the procedures of exclusion and rarefaction, which characterize discourses of truth, turns out to reside in the very fact that they attempt to conceal themselves as such. Precisely because the "exclusionary" will-to-truth hides itself behind a mask of neutral objectivity and upholds an appearance of disinterestedness is it able the more prosperously to expand. The demarcation between true knowledge and power enables the will-to-the-power-of-knowledge to parade as something different from what it "actually is," so that it may press ahead more vigorously by virtue of this very misrecognition (Foucault, 1972, pp. 219-220, 227; cf. Habermas, 1987, p. 248). In this light, it is fruitful to consider the amendation of Foucault that has been proposed by Visker (1990), who has suggested a feasible way to interpret genealogy immediately and consistently as critical theory. Rather than allowing the disclosure of the constitutive preconditions of orders of knowledge to degenerate into a critique of all conceivable order, he argues that one may confront these orders with the fact that they "objectivistically misrecognize their conditions of possibility. Specific orders or systems are only capable of functioning as a result of the mystification of the exclusionary practices by which they are conditioned. Discourses are tempted to deny their discursive character in order to distract attention away from the fact that their objects are not immediately given by reality. They feel threatened by their own selectivity and exclusivity and hence have an interest in universalizing themselves, that is, in blurring or erasing their own contextual boundaries (Visker, 1990, pp. 142-143). One may conclude that, if the social sciences create order in human relationships by offering propositions that claim general validity, it is not so much this performative, ordering function itself that is at issue, but the way in which this performative effect is "withheld" by pretenses of general validity with which such ordering statements are charged. Taken by themselves, orders are simultaneously productive and repressive; their functions of enablement and constraint are circularly correlated. Exclusion of alternative orders is therefore inevitable and by itself does not constitute a reproach against the order that is contingently produced by it (Visker, 1990, p. 166). Objectivistic legitimations, however, yield an epistemological surplus that enables a specific order to be depicted and lived as the only feasible and imaginable one, thus promoting its naturalization or reification.[19] Foucaldian genealogy is primordially a machine de guerre against such reifications and against the forms of disciplinary knowledge power that are nourished by them. It studies history in order to trace through how a certain order has become a self-evident one,[20] presupposing ab initio that it is experienced as alien and is approached from the outside. This also implies that genealogy does not offer a methodology in the strict sense of a universalizable organon of knowledge production or a toolbox that remains indifferent to its various users. The "historical knowledge of struggles" that genealogy strives to assemble rather requires the presence of a knowledge subject that occupies a specific interest-bound position in the contemporary knowledge struggle: the position of the stranger, who cannot choose but to resist specific historically constituted self-evidences and is motivated to trace their origins in order to resist them more effectively. Foucault explicitly conceives of this critical historization of necessities, which are experienced as "strange" and superfluous, as a direct continuation of the grand quest for freedom and autonomy, which is inscribed in the Enlightenment project (Foucault, 1984b). A typically modern critical subject is a person who consistently inquires after the contemporary limits of the necessary and attempts to invent himself in a permanent critique of our historical era. Criticism is reflecting and working upon our limits (cf. Foucault, 1991a, p. 59ff). But there is no reason why it should not adventure beyond the Kantian destruction of classical metaphysics. Critique is not so much the stipulation of the universal and necessary conditions of possibility of knowledge, but an investigation of the possible transgression of limits, including those of Kantian rationalism itself (Dreyfus & Rabinow, 1986). Hence the heritage of the Enlightenment should not so much be sought in its doctrinal elements, in the defense of something like an essential kernel of rationality, but instead in a certain ethos, a certain lifestyle that is critically poised toward the "contemporary limits of the necessary." Instead of having formal structures with a universalistic tenor determine what we can and cannot do, we ought to investigate the possibility "of no longer being, doing, or thinking what we are, do, or think," in order to give new impetus to "the undefined work of freedom" (Foucault, 1984b; 1988b, p. 10). CONCLUSIONS In this text I have made an effort to present a consistent user's guide to Foucault, which in some respects violates the letter and goes beyond the book(s), but which appears tolerably consistent with the skeptical ethics of knowledge and life conduct, which occupy the center of his philosophy. First I have accentuated the epistemological-political double play of pouvoir/savoir, which extends and complicates the idea of a circular alliance between knowledge and power by that of a similar circularity between the productive and repressive functions of both knowledge and power. From the outset, I have taken care to disengage myself both from a reductionist and from a normatively agnostic interpretation of Foucault's grounding principle, in order to make overtures to a notion of"duality," which not only cast aside the dualisms of knowledge and power and that of production and repression, but which also pretended to escape from the classical logical divorce between facts and values. The normative complexity of knowledge and power that was thereby installed could then be joined to a minimal skeptical ethic in which good and evil were seen to cruise in close vicinity. If the principle of truth power or knowledge politics exemplifies a natural proximity between empirical and normative judgments, it is more than a mere representation of the world, but actively intervenes in it. The (re)description of the world co-produces reality itself. Rather than supplying "ostensive" or indicative representations of reality, the principle of knowledge politics introduces performative representations that urge the transformation of reality in the direction indicated by the definition itself (cf. Latour, 1986, pp. 272-273). "Performativity" is a convenient label for the knowledge-political ordering effect that results from the simultaneity and indigenous cohesion of empirical descriptions and normative evaluations that do not require transcendental justification (Pels, 1990, p. 40). The relativistic circle that is thus projected is not a vicious one.[21] The principle of knowledge politics can only escape the reflexive paradox and still serve as lever for a nontrivial critique of ideology when it offers itself as a criterion of truth. Of course one may shrug one's shoulders at what looks like a form of opportunism that is supported by a self-proclaimed dogma. Doing so, one would fail to notice that the principle of knowledge politics itself is cast as a knowledge-political proposal that waives all claims for an obligatory epistemological foundation precisely on account of its self-conscious performativity, and that, in consequence, the opportunistic critique of those who prove themselves unable to grasp the "truth" of this principle does nowhere appeal to an independent reality that transcends the interpretive circle itself. The critical distinction between discourses or power complexes that "objectivistically misrecognize" themselves and discourses that do not can only be established from a knowledge-political perspective. This applies with equal force to the critical difference between discourses that fail to appreciate their own circularity and locality and discourses that realize and accept it. If applied to historiography, this idea about the circular logic of interpretation suggests the legitimacy of a form of "critical presentism." Because one cannot jump over one's hermeneutic point of departure, the present remains in a sense epistemologically privileged. But because our contemporary culture is categorized as multiple and decentered, Whig history is avoided and ample room is given to narrative pluralism. The "instability" of the knowing subject, which can no longer base its historical narrative upon a solidly grounded identity, is enhanced by its incapacity to experience the present as a standpoint "outside of time." Historiography may then adopt the posture of retrojective self-recognition--a view that tends to run counter to Foucault's stated purposes. An essentialist presentism produces tall stories according to which the past supplies incontrovertible evidence for our present excellence and of the necessity of our future calling. A relativist presentism narrates small stories, which reconstruct the past in the light of local problems and time-bound knowledge-political interests. It is at this point that my user's guide departs most clearly from the intellectual markers set down by Foucault himself. In the above, I have already braced myself against expressions that could be interpreted in an empiristic, historistic, and normatively agnostic fashion. Instead, I have attempted to reconstruct genealogy as a minimally normative, critical-presentist, reflexive, and antiobjectivistic mode of analysis. These interpretative maneuvers have enlarged the distance between my own alternative and the type of differentialism that offers the most natural vehicle for Foucault's empiricist and historicist leanings. This differentialism and its pulverizing positivism remain ever at odds with a skeptical life ethic that is not infused by neutrality but by awareness of the normative proximity of good and evil. Genealogy's critical reversal of values and truths should not issue in a simple hurray for the opposite party, but should free the stage for new strategies and a new type of mobility (Foucault, 1988a, p. 120). If criticism ends in a mere reversal of pro and contra, things remain in place and nothing moves. According to Foucault, the veritable work of the "historian of the present" has only begun as soon as he can also demonstrate the "false unity," the illusory nature of the "good" side, the side with which he has taken sides. If "everything is dangerous," even the good side, we must not impassively leave things as they are, because we have always something to do (Dreyfus & Rabinow, 1982, pp. 231-232). It is this "active relativism," this skeptical politics of knowledge, which more than anything else defines the continuing enchantment and intrigue of Foucault's work. NOTES 1. Anthony Giddens has introduced this slogan in order to combat another dilemmatic antinomy: that which separates action theory from structural theory (e.g., Giddens, 1984, pp. xx-xxi). His idea of the "duality of structure" sensitizes to the simultaneously enabling and constraining effects of social institutions. My formulations also acknowledge the influence of Latour (1990, 1993), who has suggested the term "irreductionism" (Latour, 1984, p. 177ff). 2. Duality and coincidence are hence not equivalent with identity or osmosis. Keenan speaks about the "difficult dash" that simultaneously joins and separates knowledge and power; "the dash is not a sign of equivalence, nor does it mark a covert dissimulation" (Keenan, 1987, pp. 12-13). Foucault has remarked that "when I read the thesis . . . 'Knowledge is power' or 'Power is knowledge,' I begin to laugh, since studying their relation is precisely my problem" (1983, in Kelly, 1994, pp. 132-133). That there is tension (residual?) and room (how much?) between the two concepts is also suggested by the following programmatic question: "How can the growth of capabilities be disconnected from the intensification of power relations?" (Foucault, 1984b, p. 48). Cf. Barnes's view that knowledge and power are "one and the same thing" (1988, p. 169). 3. While the vocabulary of ideology displays a nostalgia for a transparent, uncontaminated form of knowledge, the vocabulary of repression bespeaks of a similar nostalgia for a form of power "innocent of all coercion, discipline, and normalization" (Foucault, 1980, p. 117). 4. Cf. Connolly (1993, p. 366): "To reach 'beyond' the politics of good and evil is not to liquidate ethics but to become ashamed of the transcendentalization of conventional morality." 5. This is an example offered by Foucault himself (Connoly, 1993, p. 367). 6. Connolly (1993) has precisely located the Foucaldian challenge to conventional morality as residing in this destabilization of the fixed transcendental dualism of good and evil, in pursuit of a higher, more generous ethical sensibility that does no longer constitute difference as evil, but is able to embrace it in relations of "agonistic respect." Cf. more extensively, Connly (1991). 7. Cf. also Foucault's insistence that uncovering the conditions of acceptability of a discursive system cannot be separated from recognizing what made it difficult to accept it, "its arbitrariness in terms of knowledge, its violence in terms of power, in short, its energy" (1990/1994, p. 76). 8. Fraser finds Foucault's work normatively confused because he "misunderstands . . . the way that norms function in social description . . . (and) fails to appreciate the degree to which the normative is embedded in and infused throughout the whole of language at every level" (Fraser, 1989, pp. 30-31). But such a normative embeddedness is quite compatible with the methodological import of Foucaldian genealogy as I read it here. I agree with Dreyfus and Rabinow's contention (1986, p. 115) that Foucault "does not propound a normative theory but that his work certainly has a normative thrust." Indeed, Foucault facilitates a more radical version of the value-fact proximity than Fraser considers possible. 9. Connolly (1993, pp. 369, 373) employs terms such as "transcendental egoism" and "transcendental narcissism" in order to critically identify the "certification" of contingent identifies by their transformation into naturalized or ontological necessities. Put more simply: Critics such as Habermas fall prey to the (universal?) temptation to universalize their own rationalized personal experience, in order to escape its essential contingency. This, perhaps, is what moralizing is all about: It normatively magnifies and "necessitates" one's own life situation and its sociological and psychological limitations, while simultaneously erasing this generative experience from one's moral conscience. Moralizing hence implies both a self-effacement and a self-magnification; both an escape from self and a tendency to think that all others are essentially similar to oneself (which spreads the moral costs of a difficult identity). 10. These renderings better capture what Foucault means by "desinvolture appliquee" and "desinvolture staidest" than the present English translation "studied casualness" (Foucault, 1972, p. 234). They are also closer to the "relentless erudition" demanded of genealogists in (Foucault, 1977b, p. 140). 11. "History protects us from historicism from a historicism that calls on the past to resolve the questions of the present" (Foucault, 1984a, p. 250). 12. Dreyfus and Rabinow (1982) likewise underscore the "unequivocal and unabashed contemporary orientation" of the genealogical method, which at all times starts out with a diagnosis of the current situation (pp. 119, 232, 253). 13. Cf. Dews (1987, p. 180ff) for a parallel critique. Cohen and Arato (1992) likewise identify a vicious circle: "Either the norms and projects articulated by social movements are strategies of counterpower and as such have no greater normative claim than those of other power seekers, or they simply reproduce the existing discourses of power. For a critical theory with a partisan intent, as Foucault's surely is, this is indeed a serious flaw" (pp. 295-296). 14. Cf. also Dews (1987, pp. 189-191) who opines that Foucault's relativism is in tension with his political involvement, which continually forces him to sever the intimate connection between knowledge and power in order to be able to separate the illusory knowledge that is allied to power from the authentic knowledge that is allied to "resistance." In my interpretation such a break does not exist. "Resistance thinking" does not cease to be authentic, even if it in turn displays a (different, not less intimate) conjugation of knowledge and power. Cf. Hiley (1988, p. 86ff) for a similar view. 15. "The problem is not of trying to dissolve [relations of power] in the utopia of a perfectly transparent communication, but to give oneself the rules of law, the techniques of management, and also the ethics, the ethos, the practices of the self, which would allow these games of power to be played with a minimum of domination" (Foucault, 1988b, p. 18). 16. On the proximity of the discourses of domination and liberation, see also Foucault (1972; 1978; 1984a, 10p. 96, 156-157). 17. "Bad" knowledge fears and conjures away its own circularity; "good" knowledge acknowledges and celebrates it. 18. In this sense, Foucault rejects all immanent critique, while Habermas's accusatory identification of "performative contradictions" typically presupposes its legitimacy. The idea of a performative contradiction projects an exogenous standard of evaluation into the adversary's work, which is subsequently exposed as riven by self-contradiction. Through such fifth column infiltration, the cognitive strength of the adversary is sapped from the inside. What appears as an indigenous flaw is in fact insinuated from the outside. The ventriloquist critic exonerates and absents himself from his projection, in that the contradiction is not between himself and his opponent, but between the opponent's own sayings and his actual doings. In this fashion, performative contradictions are essentially circular, but by their very grammar manage to conceal this circularity. 19. Universalist claims, in my reading, are exaggerated attempts to carry local claims a little further, to enlarge their field of acceptance, to hold a broader audience. They are a power argument in intellectual negotiations. Universalists systematically overstate their case, because rights of maximum diffusion are claimed against all the world. Universalism performatively anticipates what can only be realized incrementally, contingently, practically, imperfectly. 20. What Foucault aims at is to write the history of the "objectivation of objectivities" (Foucault, 1991b, p. 86). 21. By itself, the idea of a productive argumentative circle offers an intriguing example of the proximity and interlacing of good and evil, which I take to be a distinctive feature of a skeptical ethic of knowledge politics. REFERENCES Armstrong, T. J., (Ed.). (1992). Michel Foucault: Philosopher. New York: Routledge. Barnes, B. (1988). The nature of power. Cambridge: Polity Press. Bernstein, R. (1994). Foucault: Critique as a philosophic ethos. In M. Kelly (Ed.), Critique and power. Recasting the Foucault,/Habermas debate (pp. 211-241). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Bourdieu, P. (1989). The corporatism of the universal. The role of intellectuals in the modem world. Telos, 81, 99-110. Bourdieu, P. (1991). Les regles de l'art. Paris: Seuil. Callon, M., Law, J., & Rip, A. (FzzAs.). (1986). Mapping the dynamics of science. London: MacMillan. Cohen, J. L., & Arato, A. (1992). Civil society and political theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Connolly, W. E. (1985). Taylor, Foucault, and otherness. Political Theory, 13(3), 365-376. Connolly, W. E. (1991). Identity/Difference. Democratic negotiations of political paradox. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Connolly, W. E. (1993). Beyond good and evil. The ethical sensibility of Michel Foucault. Political Theory, 21(3), 365-389. Dews, P. (1987). Logics of disintegration. London: Verso. Dreyfus, H., & Rabinow, P. (1982). Michel Foucault. Beyond structuralism and hermeneutics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Dreyfus, H., & Rabinow, P. (1986). What is maturity? Habermas and Foucault on "What is Enlightenment?". In D.C. Hoy (Ed.), Foucault: A critical reader. Oxford: Blackwell. Foucault, M. (1965). Madness and civilization. New York: Pantheon. Foucault, M. (1972). The Archaeology of Knowledge. New York: Harper Torchbooks. Foucault, M. (1977a). Discipline and punish. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books. Foucault, M. (1977b). Nietzsche, genealogy, history. In D. F. Bouthard (Ed.), Language, counter-memory, practice. Oxford: Blackwell. Foucault, M. (1978). The history of sexuality I: An introduction. New York: Random House. Foucault, M. (1980). Power/Knowledge: Selected interviews and other writings 1972-1977 (C. Gordon, Ed.). New York: Pantheon. Foucault, M. (1982). The subject and power. In H. Dreyfus & P. Rabinow (Eds.), Michel Foucault. Beyond structuralism and hermeneutics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Foucault, M. (1983). Structuralism and post-structuralism. Telos, 55. Foucault, M. (1984a). Space, knowledge, and power. In P. Rabinow (Ed.), The Foucault reader. New York: Pantheon. Foucault, M. (1984b). What is enlightenment? In P. Rabinow (Ed.), The Foucault reader. New York: Pantheon. Foucault, M. (1988a). Politics, philosophy, culture. Interviews and other writings 1977-1984 (L. D. Kritzman, Ed.). New York: Routledge. Foucault, M. (1988b). Truth, power, self. In L. Martin, H. Gutman, & P. Hutton (Eds.), Technologies of the self. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press. Foucault, M. (1991a). Politics and the study of discourse. In G. Burcheil, C. Gordon, & P. Miller (Eds.), The Foucault effect. Studies in governmentality. London: Harvester. Foucault, M. (1991b). Questions of method. In G. Burcheil, C. Gordon, & P. Miller (Eds.), The Foucault effect. Studies in governmentality. London: Harvester. Foucault, M. (1994). Kritiek en Verlichting (Dutch Translation of Qu'est-ce que la critique? [Critique et Auflklarung]) [What is Critique? Critique and enlightenment]. Krisis. Tijdschrift voor filosofie, 56 (September). (Original work published 1990) Fraser, N. (1989). Unruly practices. Cambridge: Polity. Giddens, A. (1984). The constitution of society. Cambridge: Polity. Gouldner, A. W. (1973). For sociology. London: Allen Lane. Habermas, J. (1987). The philosophical discourse of modernity. Cambridge: Polity. Habermas, J. (1992). Faktizitat und Geltung [Facticity and validity]. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. Hiley, D. R. (1988). Philosophy in question. Essays on a Pyrrhonian theme. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Honneth, A. (1994). Foucault's theory of society: A systems-theoretic dissolution of the Dialectic of Enlightenment. In M. Kelly (Ed.), Critique and power Recasting the Foucault/Habermas debate (pp. 243-282). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Keenan, T. (1987). The "paradox" of knowledge and power: Reading Foucault on a bias. Political Theory, 15(1), 5-37. Kelly, M. (1994). Foucault, Habermas, and the self-referentiality of critique. In M. Kelly (Ed.), Critique and power Recasting the Foucault/Habermas debate (pp. 365-400). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Kunneman, H. (1986). De waarheidstrechter. Meppel: Boom. Lacroix, B. (1981). Durkheim et le politique. Paris: Presses de la Fondation Nationale des sciences politiques. Latour, B. (1983). Give me a laboratory and I will raise the world. In K. Knorr & M. Mulkay (Eds.), Science observed. London: Sage. Latour, B. (1984). Les microbes. Guerre etpaix. Paris: Fayard. Latour, B. (1986). The powers of association. In J. Law (Ed.), Power, action, and belief. A new sociology of knowledge ?. London: Routledge. Latour, B. (1987). Science in action. Milton Keynes: Open University Press. Latour, B. (1990). Postmodem? No, simply amodem! Steps towards an anthropology of science. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 21,165-171. Latour, B. (1991). The impact of science studies on political philosophy. Science, Technology, and Human Values, 16(1), 3-19. Latour, B. (1993). We have never been modern. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Law, J. (1986). Power, action, and belief. A new sociology of knowledge?. London: Routledge. Lukes, S. (1982). Introduction. In Durkheim (Ed.), The Rules of Scientific Method. London: MacMillan. McCarthy, T. (1994). The critique of impure reason: Foucault and the Frankfurt School. In M. Kelly (Ed.), Critique and power. Recasting the Foucault, Habermas debate (pp. 243-282). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Pels, D. (1983). Het project als object. Durkheim's kennispolifiek in relafivistisch perspectief [The project as object. Durkheim and the politics of theory]. Amsterdams Sociologisch Tijdschrift, 10(1), 51-91. Pels, D. (1987). Macht of eigendom? Een kwestie van intellectuele rivalitelt. Amsterdam: Van Gennep. Pels, D. (1990). De natuurlijke saamhorigheid van feiten en waarden. [The natural proximity of facts and values]. Kennis & Methode, 14(1), 14-43. Pels, D. (1993). Het democratisch verschil. Jacques de Kadt en de nieuwe elite. Amsterdam: Van Gennep. Pels, D. (1995). Knowledge politics and anti-politics? Toward a critical appraisal of Bourdieu's concept of intellectual autonomy. Theory and Society, 24, 79-104. Pels, D. (in press). Property or power? A study in intellectual rivalry. New York: Guilford. Rabinow, P. (Ed.). (1984). The Foucault reader. New York: Pantheon. Rajchman, J. (1985). Foucault. The freedom of philosophy. New York: Columbia University Press. Rochlitz, R. (I 992). The aesthetics of existence: Post-conventional morality and the theory of power in Michel Foucault. In T J. Armstrong (Ed.), Michel Foucault: Philosopher. New York: Routledge. Root, M. (1993). Philosophy of social science. Oxford: Blackwell. Rouse, J. (1987). Knowledge and power. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Shapin, S. (1994). A social history of truth. Gentility, credibility, and scientific knowledge in seventeenth-century England. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Taylor, C. (1985). Connolly, Foucault, and truth. Political Theory, 13(3), 377-385. Taylor, C. (1986). Foucault on freedom and truth. In D.C. Hoy (Ed.), Foucault: A critical reader. Oxford: Blackwell. Visker, R. (1990). Genealogie als kritiek. Michel Foucault en de menswetenschappen. Meppel: Boom. ~~~~~~~~ By DICK PELS University of Amsterdam _________________ Copyright of American Behavioral Scientist is the property of Sage Publications Inc. and its content may not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written permission. However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual use. Source: American Behavioral Scientist, Jun/Jul95, Vol. 38 Issue 7, p1018, 24p. Item Number: 9508010123
Kindly click here to return
to Foucault Page
Kindly click here to return to Academic Interests
Please click here to return to Additional
Information
page last updated 28 October 2004
Copyright © 2004 Miguel B. Llora, MA. All Rights Reserved.
Best viewed on Internet Explorer 5.x or later at a minimum of 1024 x 768 resolution