Magazine: American Behavioral Scientist, JUNE-JULY 1995

                  
   Record: 1
   95080101230002764219950601
   
   Title: The politics of critical description.
   Subject(s): POWER (Philosophy); FOUCAULT, Michel -- Criticism &
   interpretation; KNOWLEDGE, Theory of
   Source: American Behavioral Scientist, Jun/Jul95, Vol. 38 Issue 7,
   p1018, 24p
   Author(s): Pels, Dick
   Abstract: Analyzes the implications of Michael Foucault's genealogy of
   power and knowledge to delineate a conception of knowledge politics.
   Confounding of the idea of circular alliance between knowledge and
   power; Characteristics of the projected relativistic circle;
   Implications of circular logic of interpretation to critical
   presentism.
   AN: 9508010123
   ISSN: 0002-7642
   Full Text Word Count: 11973
   Database: Academic Search Elite
   
                    THE POLITICS OF CRITICAL DESCRIPTION
                                      
      Recovering the Normative Complexity of Foucault's pouvoir/savoir
                                      
   The slogan that scientific knowledge is a form of politics "continued
   by other means" harbors an intuition that, despite its disrespectful
   content, can already pride itself upon a respectable intellectual
   heritage. In our century, strong traditions of political correctness,
   of both left-wing and right-wing origin, have dedicated themselves to
   the demasque of avowedly disinterested products of science as ever so
   many instances of a bourgeois, antinational, patriarchal, or racist
   knowledge politics, and have engaged in drives to repoliticize science
   from the standpoint of the "proletariat," "the people," "the race," or
   various other allegedly exploited and excluded groups. Resistance
   against such political rectification, as soon as it moved beyond
   classical defenses of the value-free nature of science, has in turn
   sought appeal to a "politics of science" or a politics of rationality.
   Gouldner's "politics of the mind" was an ambiguous attempt to play in
   both registers at once and to defend science against politics by
   political means (Gouldner, 1973, p. 82ff). Bourdieu has placed a
   rather similar bet in advancing his less rationalistic, more
   interest-committed notion of a "Realpolitik of Reason" (Bourdieu,
   1989, 1991; Pels, 1995).
   
   In recent decades, this idea of knowledge politics has acquired a
   distinctly more radical profile, while the analytical focus has also
   been redirected more intensely from the external liaisons toward the
   internal workings of science. As early as Marx and Nietzsche, and
   certainly since Mannheim's work, the sociology and psychology of
   knowledge have of course been attentive to quasi-political drives and
   mechanisms governing the production of knowledge and science. Only
   recently, however, programmatic research has been building up that
   focuses on the myriad ways in which scientific claims themselves
   become power-charged and turn into the prize of intrascientific
   straggles. One example is provided by critical reassessments of the
   "politics of theory" which has been invested in the demarcation work
   of the Durkheimian school in sociology (Lacroix, 1981; Lukes, 1982;
   Pels, 1983). Other instances are provided by the philosophical
   critique of Enlightenment rationalism as conducted by Foucault,
   Derrida, Lyotard, Rorty, and others; by Bourdieu's agonistic field
   theory of science; and by the epistemological writings of feminists
   such as Fox Keller, Harding, and Haraway. Not least, the political
   metaphor has made solid conquests in the constructivist social studies
   of science as practiced by Bloor, Collins, Knorr, Woolgar, Callon, and
   Latour. It is here that the Clausewitzean dictum most pointedly
   sustains a strict refusal to disengage cognitive content and social
   context, and a determined effort to grasp the shape and operation of
   those "other means" with which science-as-politics is supposedly
   continued (e.g., Callon, Law, & Rip, 1986; Latour, 1983, 1987).
   
   It is hard to pinpoint with exactitude to what extent this new
   analytical radicalism has been inspired by Michel Foucault's genealogy
   of power/ knowledge, as he has developed it from the early 1970s to
   his early death in 1984. Many of the radical approaches, to be sure,
   acknowledge the diffuse but deep-reaching impact of his writings
   (e.g., Latour, 1991; Law, 1986; Rouse, 1987; Shapin, 1994).
   Notwithstanding such wide repercussions, however, Foucault's grounding
   intuition about the irreducible mutual implication of power and
   knowledge continues to pose a delicate epistemological riddle, which,
   in one commentator's words, has often functioned "as a kind of
   phantasmatic blank space, to be filled in with the hopes and desires
   of the interpreter" (Keenan, 1987, p. 12). An impressive phalanx of
   critics has meanwhile dismissed it as a "performative contradiction"
   (Habermas, 1987), a "vicious circle" (Cohen & Arato, 1992), as
   "normatively confused" (Fraser, 1989), and as "paradoxical and
   ultimately incoherent" (Taylor, 1985, 1986). An equally impressive
   line of supporters have countered such contestations by foregrounding
   the critical energy and ethical sensibility of Foucault's genealogical
   project (e.g., Bernstein, 1994; Connolly, 1985, 1993; Dreyfus and
   Rabinow, 1982, 1986; Rajchman, 1985). What then to make of the
   "difficult dash" (Keenan, 1987) that joins and separates knowing and
   doing, cognition and force, truth and power?
   
   My present attempt to reconstruct this intrigue departs from an
   awareness that Foucault's inconsistencies and contradictions, as
   publicized in recent debates, cannot satisfactorily be resolved
   without distancing oneself from some of his formulations, whereas on
   other points of contention he should be kept more strictly at his
   word. While departing from Foucault, I will hence also turn (back)
   against him; and contrary to the commodious prejudice that elevates a
   lack of system into a principal virtue of Foucaldian style, I will
   work my way toward a plausibly harmonious and rounded interpretation.
   Far from claiming to present an hermetic solution to the
   power/knowledge riddle, however, my aim is to propose a tolerably
   consistent way of handling or using Foucault, which may be helpful in
   delineating a more robust and empirically fruitful conception of
   "knowledge politics." Such streamlining will become especially
   apparent where I will reinterpret the genealogical intuition in an
   "irreductionist" and "minimally normative" direction, in order to
   transcend the classical divorce between facts and values, and to
   suggest a normative complexity in the analysis of knowledge and power
   which acknowledges the closeness, rather than the distance, between
   their "good" and "evil" aspects.
   
                          FROM DUALISM TO DUALITY
                                      
   Like all principles that make a difference, Foucault's principle of
   pouvoir/ savoir, or of the indissoluble entanglement of knowledge and
   power, harbors both a destructive and a constructive impulse. First,
   it polemicizes against the venerable philosophical tradition extending
   all the way from the "great Platonic divorce" between truth and power
   to modern "humanism," which deploys both concepts as quintessential
   antipodes (Foucault, 1972, pp. 218, 232; 1980, pp. 51-52). Second, it
   counteracts an equally venerable tradition in political and juridical
   philosophy, which preferably connotates the exercise of power with
   repression, exclusion, submission, and censure. Put more
   constructively, Foucault's pouvoir/savoir reconfigures the semantic
   field by offering a new definition of knowledge and a new definition
   of power. The idea of their intrinsic, constitutive, or circular
   coalition initiates a dual conception of knowledge that emphatically
   incorporates the inner ambiguities and dark underside of rationality.
   Simultaneously, by highlighting its productive next to its repressive
   functioning, a similar duality is installed in the conception of
   power.
   
   These two great Nietzschean themes of the repressive face of reason
   and the productive face of (the will to) power immediately presuppose
   and condition one another. It is precisely this epistemological double
   play that has so far received insufficient notice in the extensive
   literature that has been triggered by Foucault's work. It is
   profitable, however, to consider them as a conceptual couple that
   should be more intimately "thought together." Because the
   desublimation of reason moves in step with a rehabilitation of the
   traditional conception of power, their former hierarchical antinomy is
   absorbed in a new epistemological and normative equilibrium. Truth and
   power (its traditional "other") acquire comparable, if not equal
   philosophical status and are much more closely intertwined. Although
   (the quest for) truth reveals an intrinsic impurity, and is
   "downgraded" through the direct complicity with its traditional dark
   side, (the will to) power rises in epistemological prestige once it
   acquires cardinal functions in the production of truth, reality, and
   desire.
   
   This simultaneous "evening out" of the epistemological balance and
   contraction of the previous polarity work toward the same end:
   duality. Duality refers to the tempering of the normative energies of
   an established conceptual asymmetry in a generative coalition that
   yields a new, and weaker, principle of discrimination (Pels, 1987,
   1990, 1993). While the traditionally positive becomes less positive,
   the traditionally negative also becomes less negative; positivity and
   negativity are resettled in much closer vicinity, without losing their
   normative tension. One of the most intriguing features of the
   Foucaldian principle of pouvoir/savoir is perhaps that precisely by
   breaking the dominant binary code and melting knowledge and power into
   such a close coalition, the productive and repressive dimensions of
   both power and knowledge are now considered mutually constitutive
   rather than antithetical. This is enough to instill in both concepts a
   radical epistemological and ethical complexity.
   
   It is not hard to reap citations in order to illustrate this
   equilibrating double play. In his 1970 inaugural lecture, Foucault
   precisely articulates the dangerous and violent character of speech
   and suggests that the order of discourse is characteristically
   constituted by miscellaneous procedures of exclusion, rarefaction, and
   misrecognition, which simultaneously exorcise and occlude these
   intrinsic powers and dangers. What appears before our eyes "is only
   the truth of wealth, fertility, and sweet strength in all its
   insidious universality. In contrast, we are unaware of the prodigious
   machinery of the will to truth, with its vocation of exclusion"
   (Foucault, 1972, p. 220). Knowledge can no longer be conceived in
   terms of a neutral, disinterested reflection of objective reality.
   Interpretation equals conquest: Instead of uncovering objective
   meanings, interpretation is "the violent or surreptitious
   appropriation of a system of rules, which in itself has no essential
   meaning." A reflexive, genealogical self-questioning of the work of
   historical interpretation reveals that historical consciousness is not
   free from passion or interest, but harbors an impassioned "will to
   truth." That is to say that "all knowledge rests upon injustice (that
   there is no right, not even in the act of knowing, to truth or a
   foundation for truth) and that the instinct for knowledge is
   malicious." (Foucault, 1977b, pp. 151, 163). Discourse must be
   conceived as "a violence that we do to things, or, at all events, as a
   practice which we impose upon them" (Foucault, 1972, p. 229).
   
   If truth is presently "a thing of this world" (Foucault, 1980, p. 131)
   and has become something prosaic and commonplace, the traditional
   mundanity of power in turn becomes less dirty and subterranean.
   Foucault's criticism of transcendental views of rationality is
   complemented by the idea that power interests exercise a productive,
   perspective-constituting function in the formation of knowledge.
   Rather than continuing the negative vocabulary of censorship,
   prohibition, and distortion, we should recognize that "power produces;
   it produces reality; it produces domains of objects and rituals of
   truth" (Foucault, 1977a, p. 194). What maintains power and makes it
   acceptable is the fact that it does not only weigh on us as a
   nay-saying force, "but that it traverses and produces things, it
   induces pleasure, forms knowledge, produces discourse" (Foucault,
   1980, p. 199). The lapidary statement that "far from preventing
   knowledge, power produces it" (p. 59) may then be read as a
   rudimentary "flashlight theory" of power, according to which objects
   of knowledge are rendered accessible only because they are delineated
   and illuminated by power drives and practices (Visker, 1990, p. 71).
   It is arguable, however, that Foucault envisages something more
   radical than such a "perspectivism of power," by suggesting a theory
   of constitution according to which reality is performatively made
   rather than merely "encountered" in its multifarious disorder. In this
   constructivism of power, both reality and the knowledge of it are
   produced in the course of and by means of the practical "violence that
   we do to things."
   
   At once I like to counter a double misapprehension to which Foucault's
   own formulations give rise, but which is also triggered by reflexes of
   the axiomatic split between knowledge and power, which he attempts to
   subvert. This misunderstanding is fostered by a twofold reductionism.
   The grounding rule that "truth isn't outside of power, or lacking in
   power" is routinely interpreted in terms of a desire to reduce
   knowledge, truth, and science to power practices, which ultimately
   stages power as a transcendental demiurge or an ontological a priori
   that is taken to be constitutive of all "true speaking." Likewise,
   Foucault is suspected of an urge to replace the repressive or
   juridical conception of power by its productive or disciplinary
   counterpart. In both dimensions, he would supposedly be concerned to
   effect a critical inversion of established models of the relationship
   between knowledge and power and of the negative and positive
   modalities of power exercise, without actually superseding the
   dualistic framework itself.
   
   It must be conceded that such misunderstandings are actively enhanced
   by Foucault's intermittent tendency to reify notions of power,
   domination, and discipline, and to assign them a transcendentally
   constitutive function (e.g., Foucault, 1977a, p. 193; 1977b, pp.
   150-151; 1978, pp. 158-159; 1980, pp. 59, 93; 1988a, p. 118). In
   various contexts, he also appears to lend epistemological primacy to
   the productive over the repressive theory of power (e.g., Foucault,
   1978, pp. 73, 85-86; 1980, pp. 59, 119), whereas other passages, such
   as the one cited above, place all emphasis upon the "malicious" rather
   than the productive nature of the "will to know." In other words,
   Foucault's genealogies regularly flirt with a critical methodology of
   renversement or inversion (Foucault, 1972, pp. 229, 231; cf. Rajchman,
   1985, p. 56). Criticisms such as those offered by Habermas (1987),
   Dews (1987), Cohen and Arato (1992), or McCarthy (1994) of the
   essentialist or ontological quality of Foucault's concept of power are
   therefore definitely on target. However, there are also reasons to
   suppose that Foucault intends to escape from this reductionist drift
   and is groping toward "irreductionist" principles, which equally
   discard the dualism of knowledge and power as that of repressive
   versus productive (knowledge) power. Foucault sometimes bends the
   stick in the other direction, but is also chased by the residual logic
   of both traditional oppositions. Still, it is much more interesting to
   interpret the "circular" coincidence of knowledge and power and that
   of production and repression as an attempt to leap twice from dualism
   to duality.[1] In both cases, this leap departs from the magnetic
   poles to the middle reaches of the force field, reallocating
   properties that were hitherto defined by the oppositional dualism.
   
   With Dreyfus and Rabinow, I consider this view of the "simultaneity"
   of knowledge and power, where neither can be explained in terms of or
   can be reduced to the other, as constituting the most radical
   dimension of Foucault's work (Dreyfus & Rabinow, 1982, pp. 114, 194,
   203; cf. Keenan, 1987, pp. 14-15).[2] Illumination of the seamy side
   of rationality does as little to replace the traditional panegyric of
   reason as does illumination of power's positivity substitute for the
   idea of negative power. In his inaugural lecture, Foucault (1972)
   already unravels the intrinsic link between the ordering of the world
   by truthful discourses and the exclusion and rarefaction that they
   inevitably bring in their train (cf. Visker, 1990, pp. 128-129). The
   will to know is simultaneously part of the danger and a tool to combat
   that danger (Rabinow, 1984, p. 7). In an interview from 1983, this
   inner ambiguity of reason is signaled in the following terms: "If
   intellectuals in general are to have a function, if critical thought
   itself has a function . . . it is precisely to accept this sort of
   spiral, this sort of revolving door of rationality that refers us to
   its necessity, to its indispensability, and at the same time, to its
   intrinsic dangers" (Foucault, 1984a, p. 249).
   
   A similar spiraling connection between "indispensability" and "danger"
   can be situated in the concept of power. In Gordon's interpretation,
   the novelty of Foucault's approach is that he locates thinking about
   power "beyond good and evil," that is, outside the force field that
   extends between a positively benign sociological model of power as the
   agency of social cohesion and normality and a more polemical
   representation of power as an instance of repression, violence, and
   coercion. In doing so, Foucault (1980, pp. 234-235) introduces a
   methodological principle of neutrality or skepticism in the analysis
   of power. It is not clear, however, in what sense neutrality and
   skepticism precisely cohere. In my view, Foucaldian skepticism is not
   exhausted by the neutralization of the dualism of enabling and
   constraining power but carries a much wider significance, whereas also
   the interconnection between productive and repressive power should be
   conceived in a more intrinsic or constitutive fashion. The revolving
   door of power is not only similar in shape to the revolving door of
   rationality: It is one and the same door.[3]
   
   That is to suggest that the principle of pouvoir/savoir, while indeed
   passing beyond established distributions of good and evil, does so in
   a very specific sense that does not signify an adieu to all normative
   deliberation in favor of dispassionate scientific description.
   Foucault's analysis is only neutral and agnostic in terms of the
   classical dualisms that he singles out for attack, and does not per se
   include a plea for normative neutrality or value-free naturalism.
   Skeptical awareness of the paradoxal proximity between rationality and
   irrationality and between productive and restrictive power, which
   results from bracketing their unmixed antithesis, does not entail the
   bracketing of all forms of ethical sensibility and purpose. Rather, it
   suggests a novel minimal normativity according to which good and evil
   no longer constitute transcendental antipodes but live together much
   more closely than is accounted for in conventional ethical discourse.
   If light and dark sides to some extent condition one another, positive
   and negative dimensions are deployed much more ambiguously than either
   a traditional sociological functionalism or a traditional ethics will
   find palatable. I believe that the fundamental skepticism that exudes
   from such an awareness of circular connections between good and evil
   stands close to the heart of Foucault's philosophical ethos (Connolly,
   1993; Rabinow, 1984, p. 47; Rajchman, 1985; Rochlitz, 1992).[4]
   
   This talk of good and evil, to be sure, reinforces a normative reading
   of the complexity that is instituted by the duality of the positive
   and the negative, according to which sociological assessments of
   indispensability and danger (or production and repression) are to some
   extent taken as secularized and "scientized" recodings of much older
   moral antinomies. When explaining that power does not operate through
   prohibition and negation, but is productive of true speaking, of the
   sexualizing of bodies or of the normalization of subjectivity,
   Foucault usually employs a "cool" sociotechnical sense of
   productivity, which appears to preclude a normative stance with regard
   to the technologies or disciplines involved. If he insists that power
   is much more than a negative instance but should be conceived as a
   productive network that runs through the entire social body, or that
   productive disciplinary power supplies the necessary basis for the
   great negative or juridical forms of power, the linkage between
   positivity and negativity appears to stand closer to the analytical
   relationship between whole and part than to the normative relationship
   between good and evil.
   
   Nevertheless, I suppose there is interpretive room for a less neutral
   or technological conception of the duality of enablement/constraint or
   that of production/repression, both in the case of knowledge and in
   that of power. In this conception, many apparently secular
   sociological antinomies (authority vs. power, agency vs. structure,
   subject vs. object, consensus vs. conflict, normal vs.
   pathological[5]) retain significant residues of the religious and
   moral distinction between good and evil and remain laterally connected
   with its manifold contemporary representations, even though dominant
   epistemologies actively repress or passively neglect such normative
   resonances. The theorem about the proximity or duality of the positive
   and the negative, in this particular sense, does not elevate
   sociological concepts (such as knowledge and power) to a generic level
   of abstraction ruled by moral indifference, but opts for a more
   intricate and demanding interpretation according to which good and
   evil cohabitate closely enough to put all naturalistic distinctions
   into epistemological disorder.[6]
   
                              FACTS AND VALUES
                                      
   Next to filing an analytic claim, the idea of the revolving door of
   knowledge power thus also carries a normative point. This entails
   that, in their turn, descriptive and normative judgments are much more
   tightly ensnared than is acknowledged by standard conceptions in
   philosophy and social-political theory (Pels, 1990; Root, 1993). Such
   a claim to interpret the central intuition of pouvoir/savoir in terms
   of a critical mixture of factual and value statements not only propels
   us into the storm center of the Foucault debate (cf. Armstrong, 1992;
   Kelly, 1994), but distances us even more pertinently from the image
   that Foucault himself has irregularly upheld of the naturalistic
   methodological import of his genealogical project. However, a
   "minimally normative" amendment of Foucault appears called for if we
   wish to cope successfully with some important objections that have
   been leveled against the "descriptivism" and "crypto-normativism" of
   his historical analyses. The most incisive and widely publicized
   critique has of course been raised by Habermas, Foucault's great
   sparring partner in the philosophical debate about the Enlightenment
   (Habermas, 1987; cf. also Bernstein, 1994; Cohen & Arato, 1992;
   Fraser, 1989; Honneth, 1994; Taylor, 1986). While acknowledging the
   legitimacy of this line of critique, I also presume that a relapse
   into the dualistic and universalistic (or "humanistic") framework from
   which Habermas operates can and should be avoided; differently put,
   that the principle of pouvoir/savoir generates an indigenous normative
   criterion for a critical theory that does not lay claim to a
   universally compelling or transcendental type of validation.
   
   Foucault's genealogies have often been read (and liberally permit such
   a reading) as products of an epistemological leap from normative
   toward straight-forwardly descriptive theory (cf. Habermas, 1987;
   Taylor, 1986). Normativity is usually interpreted as "normalization"
   (Cohen & Arato, 1992, p. 296). Habermas has typically claimed that
   Foucault systematically eludes value judgments and the more general
   issue of the justification of critique in favor of value-free
   historical explanations, and thus naturalistically reduces the
   dimension of "ought" to that of "is." Genealogical historiography, he
   has argued, confronts the mutually sealed discursive universes, which
   permit only internal strife about norms and values, and their
   underlying practices of power in a strictly descriptive,
   nonparticipatory if not ascetic manner. It brackets normative validity
   claims as well as claims to propositional truth and elopes the
   question whether some discourse and power formations can be more
   legitimate than others. Here Habermas gratefully fastens upon
   Foucault's own characterization of the genealogical temperament as a
   "felicitous positivism," and Paul Veyne's depiction of Foucault as the
   historian "in a pure state," who desires nothing further than
   stoically to announce "wie es wirklich gewesen ist" (Habermas, 1987,
   pp. 275-276, 282). Such detachment, however, ensnares Foucault in a
   major aporia. The cool facade of his radical historicism hardly
   conceals the critical passions that rage underneath. Foucault's
   normative engagement is palpable right down to his style and choice of
   words, but can nowhere be explicitly acknowledged. His reductionist
   naturalism fosters the same crypto-normativism for which he himself
   has indicted the supposedly value-free human sciences. The idea that
   there is something wrong with modern disciplinary knowledge power
   presupposes the salience of particular normative standards, and such
   standards are indeed subliminally present in Foucault's genealogies.
   However, because they are not articulated as such, Foucault falls
   victim to an "arbitrary partisanship" and an "unholy subjectivism"
   (Habermas, 1987, pp. 276, 284).
   
   Once again, it must be conceded that Foucault makes himself eminently
   vulnerable to this reproach. The expression "positivisme heureux" from
   his 1970 inaugural lecture does not fail to conjure up misgivings,
   whereas the genealogical deconstruction of moral-utopian and
   juridico-political discourses often exemplifies a strong historicist
   and positivistic drift (cf. Dews, 1987, p. 180). Against totalizing
   theories that unveil finalistic continuities of historical
   development, genealogy intends carefully to "listen to history"
   (Foucault, 1977b, p. 142) in order to study with minimal prejudice how
   knowledge power actually functions. Foucault's critique does not say
   that things are not all right as they are, but is out to show how and
   why things have become what they are (cf. Visker, 1990, pp. 111-112).
   The genealogical method performs this critical task primarily by
   revealing the historical arbitrariness of the present by demonstrating
   that that-which-is has not always existed but is the product of a
   patchwork of contingencies (Foucault, 1983, p. 206; 1977b, p. 146;
   1990/1994, pp. 74-75). Accordingly, the grounding rule of
   pouvoir/savoir itself is introduced as an apparently neutral
   proposition about its factual omnipresence. Consider the following
   characteristic and by no means isolated statement:
   
   The exercise of power perpetually creates knowledge and, conversely,
   knowledge constantly induces effects of power. . . . Modern humanism
   is therefore mistaken in drawing this line between knowledge and
   power. Knowledge and power are integrated with one another, and there
   is no point in dreaming of a time when knowledge will cease to depend
   on power; this is just a way of reviving humanism in a utopian guise.
   It is not possible for power to be exercised without knowledge, it is
   impossible for knowledge not to engender power (Foucault, 1980, p.
   52).
   
   Suspicions raised by critics such as Habermas, Fraser, Taylor, or
   Dews, that such statements represent somewhat more than mere
   empirical-historical generalizations, certainly appear justified.
   Foucault's "critical historicism" (Rabinow, 1984) does not simply add
   critique to historical analysis, but appears to presume a much more
   immediate and internal relationship between both types of endeavor.
   From a traditional conception of the logical tie between facts and
   values, it may indeed seem as if normative considerations are entirely
   swallowed by empirical generalizations. Even Habermas, who refuses the
   sharp heterogeneity between the discourses of truth and normativity,
   without ceasing to assign them to separate domains (cf. Habermas,
   1992), cannot react otherwise than by the familiar reflex of
   reproaching Foucault for sliding into a naturalistic reductionism. It
   would be more exciting, on the other hand, to inquire whether
   Foucault, rather than reducing values to facts, pulls off a more
   intriguing trick that positions him beyond the traditional playground
   of the logical dualism itself. Foucault's genealogy, if so
   interpreted, would once again effect a double epistemological leap
   away from both objective statements of fact and universalistic moral
   prescriptions in the direction of mixtures of facts and values whose
   connection is so intimate that the descriptions necessarily bring
   along their own normativity (and the other way around). Once again,
   this "natural proximity" of facts and values must be interpreted in an
   explicitly irreductionist sense (Pels, 1990).
   
   That genealogy may be fruitfully seen as a project of "critical" or
   "evaluative" description (cf. also Bernstein, 1994, p. 227; Kelly,
   1994) is borne out by a number of important suggestions. Any diagnosis
   of the present, Foucault asserts, must manage to grasp "why and how
   that-which-is might no longer be that-which-is" by following "lines of
   fragility" in the present; any description must hence always be made
   in accordance with the possible spaces of freedom, the transformative
   possibilities that the present offers (Foucault, 1984b, pp. 126-127).
   The "ironic heroization" of the present, which is characteristic of
   the ethos of modernity, its "trans figuring play of freedom with
   reality," intends to transform it "not by destroying it but by
   grasping it in what it is" --although this must not be taken in the
   sense that prescriptions are derivable from descriptions (p. 127).
   Modernity is an exercise "in which extreme attention to what is real
   is confronted with the practice of a liberty that simultaneously
   respects this reality and violates it" (p. 41). Even though Foucault
   remains somewhat enigmatic, his injunction to follow "fractures" or
   "lines of fragility" in order to discover "spaces of freedom" within
   the real appears to experiment with an irreductionist notion of the
   proximity of empirical facts and critical values, which draws both
   terms much closer together than traditional epistemology will
   allow.[7] Expressions such as "critical ontology of the present" or
   "critical ontology of ourselves" (Foucault, 1984b, p. 50) only serve
   to enhance this impression.[8]
   
   Insofar as Foucault still tends to elope an explicit justification of
   the normative implications of his genealogical reconstructions, he
   remains vulnerable to critique. But this does not at all imply, as
   Habermas and other critics demand, that Foucault is obliged to supply
   transcendentalist foundations for his normative assumptions and that
   everything that falls below this exacting standard can be written off
   in terms of "arbitrary partisanship." Neither does it seem correct, as
   Kunneman is concerned to argue, that such universalistic criteria of
   justification are implicitly present in Foucault's oeuvre; that its
   normative groundwork therefore exemplifies strong affinities with that
   of Habermas's own theory; and that the latter inadequately attends to
   the (good) reasons that Foucault might offer for renouncing a
   systematic justification thereof (Kunneman, 1986, p. 367ff). Rather,
   the most decisive reason for refusing such a justification is that
   Foucault's critique of propositional truths and prescriptive values
   precisely intends to undercut such presumptions of universalism; from
   his perspective, the call for rationalistic foundations is a type of
   "Enlightenment blackmail" (Foucault, 1984b, pp. 41-42; 1990/1994, p.
   118). His own critical project no longer seeks to identify "the
   universal structures of all knowledge or of all possible moral action"
   but fully recognizes the local, specific, and contingent nature of
   critique (Foucault, 1984b, pp. 250, 46; 1988b, p. 11; 1991b, pp.
   73-74).[9]
   
   Habermas has complained about genealogy's "irritating double play" in
   claiming for its concept of power the innocence of an empirically
   based category, while simultaneously deploying it as a grounding
   concept in a metaphysical theory of constitution (Habermas, 1987, pp.
   270, 273-274; cf. also McCarthy, 1994). This transcendental quality,
   he argues, is precisely what lends the empirical analysis of
   technologies of power their significance as a critique of rationality,
   and what secures for genealogical historiography its unmasking effect.
   Although his intuition about genealogy's double role appears correct,
   Habermas also appears to miss the very proximity between facts and
   values that was identified earlier and that both relativizes the
   claimed "innocence" of empirical inquiry and the metaphysical nature
   of Foucault's grounding of critique in a transcendental priority of
   power networks. Foucault's genealogical descriptions get by very well
   without the pretense toward objectivity, which is supported by
   functionalist sociology; neither must the synthetic coupling of
   knowledge and power inevitably be conceived in transcendental and
   aphoristic terms. The constitutive synthesis of knowledge and power is
   not ontologically framed -- at least not in the conventional sense
   (cf. Foucault, 1990/1994, p. 128) -- but assembles constative and
   normative judgments in a critical mix, which, while renouncing
   rationalistic strategies of validation, offers a perspective according
   to which discursive formations and power practices can simultaneously
   be redescribed and put to the ethical test. This enterprise does as
   little require an external justification of truth claims as it does
   pursue an external grounding of its normative assumptions.
   
                         THE HISTORY OF THE PRESENT
                                      
   In order to see why this is not as paradoxical as Habermas and other
   rationalists think it is, we may shift toward another corner of the
   debate, in order to attend to the specific manner in which Foucault's
   genealogical method mingles and balances "presentist" and
   "anti-presentist" elements. His attempt to break free from the
   customary prejudice that only values the past in terms of the here and
   now, tends to approximate him to a value-free and relativistic
   historicism that severs the epistemological link with the present in
   that it undertakes to study the past in its own context and in its own
   terms. Simultaneously, however, Foucault advocates a critical
   perspectivism that rebuilds the bridge between present and past in
   that it explicitly subordinates historical analysis to current
   interests and problematics. At the close of the first chapter of
   Discipline and Punish, for example, Foucault (1977a) wonders what is
   actually at stake in the history that he aspires to write: "Why?
   Simply because I am interested in the past? No, if one means by that
   writing a history of the past in terms of the present. Yes, if one
   means writing the history of the present" (pp. 30-31). This
   simultaneous yes and no concentrates the dilemma of Foucault's
   "critical historicism." For how can the modest vocation to "listen to
   history" be squared with the perspectival "violence" that is committed
   in historical interpretation? What is the import of the "dedicated
   boldness" or "studious audacity" that Foucault considers
   characteristic for the critical style?[10] How can genealogy be
   conducted as "anti-science" (Foucault, 1980, p. 83)?
   
   We may encircle this dilemma a little more closely in Foucault's 1971
   programmatic essay on "Nietzsche, Genealogy, History." Here, the
   genealogical method is primarily articulated in opposition to a
   finalistic metaphysics, which depicts the development of history in
   terms of singular continuities and closed totalities (Foucault, 1977b,
   p. 140). Against the solemnity of this originary metaphysics, which
   locates the essential identity and all true possibilities of things in
   their first beginnings, genealogy prefers to "listen to history" in
   order to uncover differences, deviations, discontinuities, and
   dispersions. Then it is revealed that these pontifical essences mask
   something totally different, something vulgar and mundane: Reason,
   truth, and scientific method draw a veil over chance, passion, and the
   will to power (pp. 142-145). For Foucault, presentism is equal to the
   unreflected retrojection of contemporary interests, institutions, and
   practices that are "lived" as absolute and universalistic ones, and he
   resists a retrojective historiography that encourages such "subjective
   recognitions." Knowledge does not depend on rediscovery and
   emphatically excludes the "rediscovery of ourselves." True
   historiography does no longer search for the roots of our identity but
   "introduces discontinuity into our very being" (pp. 152, 154, 162). It
   is no longer a question "of judging the past in the name of a truth
   that only we can possess in the present; but risking the destruction
   of the subject who seeks knowledge in the endless deployment of the
   will to knowledge" (p. 164).[11]
   
   It is highly improbable, therefore, that Foucault endorses a form of
   historicism that contents itself with stoically detached descriptions
   of history's capricious game of chance, with a meticulous study of the
   origins of things that would at most elicit an indirect critique of
   their ostensibly serene eternality. The genealogical project does not
   entail a relapse into empiricism or positivism, but envisages an
   anti-disciplinarian "anti-science," which is geared toward the
   emancipation of disqualified and illegitimate knowledges and wishes
   little by little to build up "strategic knowledge" (Foucault, 1980,
   pp. 83-85, 108, 145). It is anchored in a philosophical ethos
   according to which "the critique of what we are is at one and the same
   time the historical analysis of the limits that are imposed on us and
   an experiment with the possibility of going beyond them" (Foucault,
   1984b, p. 50).
   
   The fine-grained but crucial difference between a "history in terms of
   the present" and a "history of the present" does hence not concern the
   practice of critical reconstruction or retrojection as such, which
   even Foucault considers inevitable, but the absolutism or "apocalyptic
   objectivism" that tends to transform this practice into a metaphysics
   of origin and into finalistic grand narratives. Genealogy does not so
   much aim at objective analyses of historical structures of meaning or
   practices "in their own terms," but rather at reconstructive
   interpretations that issue from a contemporary critical perspective
   and that bend history to its will just like the grand totalizing
   narratives, while refusing to commit itself to their totalitarian
   foundationalist pretenses.[12] Indeed, Foucault does not hesitate to
   characterize genealogy as perspectival, engaged, and, in this specific
   sense, "malicious" and "unjust." The impulse to understand everything
   without hierarchy, without judgment or preference, is nothing but
   "sanctimonious objectivity," and stands squarely opposed to the
   Nietzschean conception of reflexivity:
   
   Historians take unusual pains to erase the elements in their work
   which reveal their grounding in a particular time and place, their
   preferences in a controversy -- the unavoidable obstacles of their
   passion. Nietzsche's version of historical sense is explicit in its
   perspective and acknowledges its system of injustice. Its perception
   is slanted, being a deliberate appraisal, affirmation, or negation; it
   reaches the lingering and poisonous traces in order to prescribe the
   best antidote. It is not given to a discrete effacement before the
   objects it observes and does not submit itself to their processes; nor
   does it seek laws, since it gives equal weight to its own sight and to
   its objects. (Foucault, 1977b, pp. 156-157)
   
   By virtue of this reflexive historical sense, genealogy is also
   capable of writing its own genealogy, in terms of a "vertical
   projection" of its own position (pp. 156-157).
   
   In this light it appears puzzling that Habermas both castigates
   Foucault for his "transcendental historicism" and simultaneously
   suspects him of an inadvertent presentism. In his view, Foucault
   wishes merely to deliver a "stoical" analysis of meaningless
   structures of power, dismissing the idea of a hermeneutic dialogue
   between the historian and the past. But, as Habermas insists, the
   explanation of technologies of power is only feasible from a
   comparative perspective, which in turn presupposes a hermeneutic point
   of departure that inevitably incorporates a diagnosis of its own time.
   Foucault is therefore guilty of the same presentism from which he
   claims to escape, in that he deploys a vertical projection of his own
   position without the concomitant reflexive consciousness (Habermas,
   1987, pp. 276-278).
   
   However, as soon as it is recognized that Foucault self-consciously
   lowers his genealogical sounding lead into the deep waters of history,
   one can only wonder at this critique. Once again such
   misunderstandings appear rooted in genealogy's unresolved tensions
   between positivistic historicism and critical perspectivism. In my
   judgment, such tensions are largely ascribable to the fierceness of
   Foucault's resistance against the tyranny of globalizing grand
   narratives, which leads him to identify their universalistic validity
   claims rather immediately with their quest for an overarching,
   unifying systematics. Historicization, for Foucault, always channels a
   double intent: It undercuts allegedly necessary and eternal
   foundations of truth and morality, while simultaneously uprooting and
   pulverizing global systems of thought in favor of highlighting
   discontinuities and differences. Hence "anti-foundationalism"
   modulates into "difference thinking" without apparent transition. But
   whereas the unmasking critique of transcendental foundations of truth,
   morality, and method presupposes a critically presentist point of
   view, the methodological preference for fragmentation, discontinuity,
   and dispersal continually pushes toward a renewed severance of this
   supply line between present and past. I see no principled reason,
   however, why "differentialism" and its positivistic drift cannot be
   cut loose from the critique of epistemological foundationalism. The
   heightened attention to historical fortuities, contingencies,
   thresholds, and coupures does not forbid the reincorporation of
   miscellaneous differences into a new narrative of continuity that is
   not a narrative of origins but is explicitly conceived as a
   knowledge-political re-construction that departs from a critical
   position in the present. In the absence of the solid anchorpoints and
   the granite foundations of tall stories, it remains perfectly possible
   to tell small stories that group differences and details into a
   consistent narrative line.
   
                           IN THE CRITICAL CIRCLE
                                      
   Small stories are not essentialist myths of origin but
   knowledge-political retrojections that are launched from an unstable,
   "uncertified" standpoint in the present. Because they depart from the
   present and orbit back through a histo-riographic detour to their
   point of departure, they are ensnared in a hermeneutic circle. Is this
   circular movement by definition a vicious one? Does the axiom of
   pouvoir/savoir escape the paradoxal relativism of a principle that
   inevitably bites its own tail? We may repeat our crucial question: How
   can the idea of an intrinsic coalition between knowledge and power
   function critically?
   
   Once again it is Habermas who deftly illuminates these problems
   through the acuity of his formulations. With his radical critique of
   rationality, it is argued, Foucault entangles himself in a reflexive
   paradox. Genealogy is concerned to explicate the origins of knowledge
   naturalistically in terms of practices of power, but this explanatory
   baseline can be reached only because Foucault ceases to think
   genealogically as soon as his own historiography comes into view. He
   is unable to explain the provenance of his own objectivity claims.
   When truth claims cannot transcend the discourse totalities in which
   they are embedded, and the latter invariably function as
   "protuberances" of power complexes, this naturally also holds for
   Foucault's own discourse. If knowledge cannot break out of the
   enchanted circle of power, and all counterpower inevitably moves
   within the horizon of the power that it combats, how then is Foucault
   able to sustain the superiority of his genealogy? Does it not exhaust
   itself in a mere "politics of theory" (Habermas, 1987, pp. 247,
   268-269, 276-281)?[13]
   
   However, this classically toned critique of the alleged performative
   "self-destruction" of relativism overshoots its mark. The reflexive
   paradox that Habermas discerns is a projection of his own theoretical
   preoccupations. "Theory politics" or "the politics of truth," for
   Foucault, is far from being a dirty word (cf. Foucault, 1980, pp.
   132-133; 1990/1994, p. 68): Nowhere does he claim a transcontextual
   objectivity or seek a transcontextual foundation that negates the
   principle of knowledge power itself. If the counterdiscourse of
   genealogy implicitly claims a larger amount of validity than the
   discourses it resists, this superiority is anyhow not derived from the
   kind of anticipatory divorce between truth and power, which is still
   upheld in the Habermasian utopia of the ideal speech situation. The
   theory of knowledge power includes an immediate reference to its own
   grounding; but this self-referentiality only "destroys" the validity
   basis of its own critical analysis if one aprioristically claims a
   type of validity that pretends to escape with all its might from the
   context of power.[14]
   
   Hence I forward the thesis that the cognitive and normative
   superiority of Foucaldian genealogy is precisely accountable to its
   refusal to divorce knowledge and power according to the "humanist"
   recipe. Rather than abandoning itself to the relativistic destruction
   of all truth rules, the principle of pouvoir/ savoir circularly
   establishes its own criterion of legitimacy. This criterion cannot be
   externally justified or anchored according to the prescriptions of
   rationalistic epistemology, in that it does not extend beyond the
   knowledge-political context of the genealogical discourse within which
   it is raised. This does not issue in a form of agnostic, value-free
   relativism that views historical formations of discourse and power as
   closed systems and excludes any and all normative comparison between
   them. On the contrary: Foucaldian genealogy offers a critically
   normative vantage point that does not only apply the principle of
   truth power to other discourses but also to itself, itself offering a
   calibration point for historical comparison.
   
   Consequently, Foucault does not oppose truth to power, but ranges one
   form of knowledge politics against another (Foucault, 1980, pp.
   132-133).[15] The foundationalist concept of truth, which sets power
   and truth in energetic opposition, is replaced by a new relativizing
   concept of truth that does no longer separate them. Different from
   what Cohen and Arato (and many others) presume, critique is not
   disempowered by an analysis that "equates discourse, reflection, and
   truth with power strategies," nor is it disqualified by the skeptical
   insight that successful resistance "merely" substitutes one strategy
   of power for another (Cohen & Arato, 1992, p. 292). The estimation
   that even an antiscience such as genealogy and the counterpowers that
   it musters will inevitably generate new forms of demarcation and
   exclusion, new elites of knowledge, and new complexes of power is the
   very opposite of an invitation to cynicism and political apathy
   (Foucault, in Dreyfus & Rabinow, 1982, pp. 231-232). Rather, it has
   fully digested the skeptical intuition that resistance against the
   established disciplinary powers, by the very need to challenge them,
   cannot but invest in the conflict and is forced to adopt some of the
   characteristics of its adversary. In this respect as well, the utopian
   purity of a Manichean struggle between the forces of good and evil,
   and of the inevitable triumph of the good, is exchanged for an
   appreciation of their unavoidable proximity. The movement that
   crusades against the established knowledge powers in order to found a
   new regime of truth does not offer an exception to this rule.[16]
   
   Once again Foucault's formulations are ambiguous, so that consistent
   interpretation necessarily borders on critical amendation. If he
   insists that the problem does not consist in how to draw the
   demarcation line between truth and untruth, but to analyze
   historically "how effects of truth are produced within discourses
   which in themselves are neither true nor false" (Foucault, 1980, p.
   118; cf. 1990/1994, p. 78), genealogy itself offers an eloquent
   exception to this agnosticist rule. Likewise, it demarcates between
   truth and falsity, although not with the help of classical truth
   rules, which demand sharp distanciation from power interests. The
   critical description of the mechanisms of disciplinary power (e.g., of
   "true speaking" as a product of confessional power techniques)
   supports an alternative conception of truth that recognizes that the
   power of (traditional) truth claims precisely issues from the
   misrecognition of their power-infused character. Henceforth all
   "truths" are rendered suspect that actively deny the social
   enforcement by which they are constituted. Against the dominant regime
   of truth, Foucault pleads in favor of a new regime, of new (and
   weaker) rules of demarcation, of "ascertaining the possibility of a
   new politics of truth." This does not entail its emancipation from
   every system of power (which remains a chimerical option) but "of
   detaching the power of truth from the forms of hegemony, social,
   economic, and cultural, within which it operates at the present time"
   (Foucault, 1980, p. 133).
   
   In order to trace the path of this critical circle, we may go on to
   examine Foucault's objection to the reductionist style of traditional
   ideology critique -- an objection that is widely shared among
   philosophers and social theorists who are routinely lumped together as
   postmodernists. Foucault and others find this concept of ideology
   fundamentally worrisome, because it is consistently erected against
   supposedly transparent conceptions of truth or reality. The new
   conception of the intrinsic alliance between truth and power, however,
   does no longer permit us to think that the world is transparent and
   immediately accessible to knowledge. Genealogy rejects the
   naturalistic premise that "under power with its acts of violence and
   its artifice, we should be able to rediscover the things themselves in
   their primitive vivacity" (Foucault, 1988b, p. 119). Simultaneously,
   however, Foucault regularly deploys the concept of ideology in a
   critical context, and refers to an underlying (?) reality that is
   being masked, distorted, or concealed (cf. Cohen & Arato, 1992, pp.
   262-263; Dews, 1987, pp. 183, 190; Foucault, 1972, pp. 227-228; 1980,
   pp. 105-108). Which new framework of truth operates as yardstick of
   judgment? Or differently put: How is an antirealist critique of
   ideology possible?
   
   It is evident from the very outset that such a critique renounces all
   capacity to unmask the knowledge position of the adversary as
   "power-infused" or "interest-committed," while excepting one's own
   position as untainted by such blemishes. The principle of truth power
   sensitizes to the power orientation of all positions: It shifts the
   epistemological balance between cognition and social interest and
   suggests a different assessment of the function of social interests
   themselves. This leaves only one logical possibility for locating a
   workable criterion of ideology critique. This criterion can only be
   posited by the principle of truth power itself, which is then licensed
   to "unmask" all conceptual positions that are unable or unwilling to
   respect this very same principle.
   
   This turns ideology critique not only into a reflexive but also into a
   circular enterprise.[17] On the one hand, such critique is capable of
   "unmasking" all discourses that consider themselves interest-free and
   conceal their commitment by knowledge-political maneuvering as
   illusory and different from what they really are. On the other hand,
   this very reduction of ideas to a context- and power-free factuality
   is impossible, in that the critique cannot break loose from its own
   normative point of departure. This is not an impossible paradox. One
   may continue to thematize the discrepancy between distorted self-image
   and reality, between what discourses say and what they actually "are"
   or "do." However, such reality judgments and the attendant imputation
   of "false consciousness" remain logically dependent upon a critical
   outsider's perspective, which is established by the principle of truth
   power itself.[18] Because objects of knowledge are invariably
   constituted by means of specific patterns of symbolic power, the
   occultation of "reality" can only be revealed from a
   knowledge-political perspective that eschews all appeals to an
   independent reality that transcends the circle. In this manner, the
   disclosure and the occultation of reality necessarily co-produce one
   another.
   
                            AGAINST OBJECTIVISM
                                      
   This circular, strictly contextualist criterion of truth therefore
   still permits the deployment of a "negative" or critical concept of
   ideology. Examples of such denunciatory critique are found in the
   destruction that Madness and Civilization (Foucault, 1965) brings upon
   the idealistic, positivistic self-image of psychology (cf. Visker,
   1990, pp. 27-28) or in the analogous demasque, in The History of
   Sexuality I, of sex as a correlate and product of the discursive
   practice of the scientia sexualis (Foucault, 1978, pp. 67-70). The
   principle of this critical analysis is generalized in Foucault's
   inaugural lecture, where the "sly" nature of the procedures of
   exclusion and rarefaction, which characterize discourses of truth,
   turns out to reside in the very fact that they attempt to conceal
   themselves as such. Precisely because the "exclusionary" will-to-truth
   hides itself behind a mask of neutral objectivity and upholds an
   appearance of disinterestedness is it able the more prosperously to
   expand. The demarcation between true knowledge and power enables the
   will-to-the-power-of-knowledge to parade as something different from
   what it "actually is," so that it may press ahead more vigorously by
   virtue of this very misrecognition (Foucault, 1972, pp. 219-220, 227;
   cf. Habermas, 1987, p. 248).
   
   In this light, it is fruitful to consider the amendation of Foucault
   that has been proposed by Visker (1990), who has suggested a feasible
   way to interpret genealogy immediately and consistently as critical
   theory. Rather than allowing the disclosure of the constitutive
   preconditions of orders of knowledge to degenerate into a critique of
   all conceivable order, he argues that one may confront these orders
   with the fact that they "objectivistically misrecognize their
   conditions of possibility. Specific orders or systems are only capable
   of functioning as a result of the mystification of the exclusionary
   practices by which they are conditioned. Discourses are tempted to
   deny their discursive character in order to distract attention away
   from the fact that their objects are not immediately given by reality.
   They feel threatened by their own selectivity and exclusivity and
   hence have an interest in universalizing themselves, that is, in
   blurring or erasing their own contextual boundaries (Visker, 1990, pp.
   142-143).
   
   One may conclude that, if the social sciences create order in human
   relationships by offering propositions that claim general validity, it
   is not so much this performative, ordering function itself that is at
   issue, but the way in which this performative effect is "withheld" by
   pretenses of general validity with which such ordering statements are
   charged. Taken by themselves, orders are simultaneously productive and
   repressive; their functions of enablement and constraint are
   circularly correlated. Exclusion of alternative orders is therefore
   inevitable and by itself does not constitute a reproach against the
   order that is contingently produced by it (Visker, 1990, p. 166).
   Objectivistic legitimations, however, yield an epistemological surplus
   that enables a specific order to be depicted and lived as the only
   feasible and imaginable one, thus promoting its naturalization or
   reification.[19]
   
   Foucaldian genealogy is primordially a machine de guerre against such
   reifications and against the forms of disciplinary knowledge power
   that are nourished by them. It studies history in order to trace
   through how a certain order has become a self-evident one,[20]
   presupposing ab initio that it is experienced as alien and is
   approached from the outside. This also implies that genealogy does not
   offer a methodology in the strict sense of a universalizable organon
   of knowledge production or a toolbox that remains indifferent to its
   various users. The "historical knowledge of struggles" that genealogy
   strives to assemble rather requires the presence of a knowledge
   subject that occupies a specific interest-bound position in the
   contemporary knowledge struggle: the position of the stranger, who
   cannot choose but to resist specific historically constituted
   self-evidences and is motivated to trace their origins in order to
   resist them more effectively.
   
   Foucault explicitly conceives of this critical historization of
   necessities, which are experienced as "strange" and superfluous, as a
   direct continuation of the grand quest for freedom and autonomy, which
   is inscribed in the Enlightenment project (Foucault, 1984b). A
   typically modern critical subject is a person who consistently
   inquires after the contemporary limits of the necessary and attempts
   to invent himself in a permanent critique of our historical era.
   Criticism is reflecting and working upon our limits (cf. Foucault,
   1991a, p. 59ff). But there is no reason why it should not adventure
   beyond the Kantian destruction of classical metaphysics. Critique is
   not so much the stipulation of the universal and necessary conditions
   of possibility of knowledge, but an investigation of the possible
   transgression of limits, including those of Kantian rationalism itself
   (Dreyfus & Rabinow, 1986). Hence the heritage of the Enlightenment
   should not so much be sought in its doctrinal elements, in the defense
   of something like an essential kernel of rationality, but instead in a
   certain ethos, a certain lifestyle that is critically poised toward
   the "contemporary limits of the necessary." Instead of having formal
   structures with a universalistic tenor determine what we can and
   cannot do, we ought to investigate the possibility "of no longer
   being, doing, or thinking what we are, do, or think," in order to give
   new impetus to "the undefined work of freedom" (Foucault, 1984b;
   1988b, p. 10).
   
                                CONCLUSIONS
                                      
   In this text I have made an effort to present a consistent user's
   guide to Foucault, which in some respects violates the letter and goes
   beyond the book(s), but which appears tolerably consistent with the
   skeptical ethics of knowledge and life conduct, which occupy the
   center of his philosophy. First I have accentuated the
   epistemological-political double play of pouvoir/savoir, which extends
   and complicates the idea of a circular alliance between knowledge and
   power by that of a similar circularity between the productive and
   repressive functions of both knowledge and power. From the outset, I
   have taken care to disengage myself both from a reductionist and from
   a normatively agnostic interpretation of Foucault's grounding
   principle, in order to make overtures to a notion of"duality," which
   not only cast aside the dualisms of knowledge and power and that of
   production and repression, but which also pretended to escape from the
   classical logical divorce between facts and values. The normative
   complexity of knowledge and power that was thereby installed could
   then be joined to a minimal skeptical ethic in which good and evil
   were seen to cruise in close vicinity.
   
   If the principle of truth power or knowledge politics exemplifies a
   natural proximity between empirical and normative judgments, it is
   more than a mere representation of the world, but actively intervenes
   in it. The (re)description of the world co-produces reality itself.
   Rather than supplying "ostensive" or indicative representations of
   reality, the principle of knowledge politics introduces performative
   representations that urge the transformation of reality in the
   direction indicated by the definition itself (cf. Latour, 1986, pp.
   272-273). "Performativity" is a convenient label for the
   knowledge-political ordering effect that results from the simultaneity
   and indigenous cohesion of empirical descriptions and normative
   evaluations that do not require transcendental justification (Pels,
   1990, p. 40).
   
   The relativistic circle that is thus projected is not a vicious
   one.[21] The principle of knowledge politics can only escape the
   reflexive paradox and still serve as lever for a nontrivial critique
   of ideology when it offers itself as a criterion of truth. Of course
   one may shrug one's shoulders at what looks like a form of opportunism
   that is supported by a self-proclaimed dogma. Doing so, one would fail
   to notice that the principle of knowledge politics itself is cast as a
   knowledge-political proposal that waives all claims for an obligatory
   epistemological foundation precisely on account of its self-conscious
   performativity, and that, in consequence, the opportunistic critique
   of those who prove themselves unable to grasp the "truth" of this
   principle does nowhere appeal to an independent reality that
   transcends the interpretive circle itself. The critical distinction
   between discourses or power complexes that "objectivistically
   misrecognize" themselves and discourses that do not can only be
   established from a knowledge-political perspective. This applies with
   equal force to the critical difference between discourses that fail to
   appreciate their own circularity and locality and discourses that
   realize and accept it.
   
   If applied to historiography, this idea about the circular logic of
   interpretation suggests the legitimacy of a form of "critical
   presentism." Because one cannot jump over one's hermeneutic point of
   departure, the present remains in a sense epistemologically
   privileged. But because our contemporary culture is categorized as
   multiple and decentered, Whig history is avoided and ample room is
   given to narrative pluralism. The "instability" of the knowing
   subject, which can no longer base its historical narrative upon a
   solidly grounded identity, is enhanced by its incapacity to experience
   the present as a standpoint "outside of time." Historiography may then
   adopt the posture of retrojective self-recognition--a view that tends
   to run counter to Foucault's stated purposes. An essentialist
   presentism produces tall stories according to which the past supplies
   incontrovertible evidence for our present excellence and of the
   necessity of our future calling. A relativist presentism narrates
   small stories, which reconstruct the past in the light of local
   problems and time-bound knowledge-political interests.
   
   It is at this point that my user's guide departs most clearly from the
   intellectual markers set down by Foucault himself. In the above, I
   have already braced myself against expressions that could be
   interpreted in an empiristic, historistic, and normatively agnostic
   fashion. Instead, I have attempted to reconstruct genealogy as a
   minimally normative, critical-presentist, reflexive, and
   antiobjectivistic mode of analysis. These interpretative maneuvers
   have enlarged the distance between my own alternative and the type of
   differentialism that offers the most natural vehicle for Foucault's
   empiricist and historicist leanings.
   
   This differentialism and its pulverizing positivism remain ever at
   odds with a skeptical life ethic that is not infused by neutrality but
   by awareness of the normative proximity of good and evil. Genealogy's
   critical reversal of values and truths should not issue in a simple
   hurray for the opposite party, but should free the stage for new
   strategies and a new type of mobility (Foucault, 1988a, p. 120). If
   criticism ends in a mere reversal of pro and contra, things remain in
   place and nothing moves. According to Foucault, the veritable work of
   the "historian of the present" has only begun as soon as he can also
   demonstrate the "false unity," the illusory nature of the "good" side,
   the side with which he has taken sides. If "everything is dangerous,"
   even the good side, we must not impassively leave things as they are,
   because we have always something to do (Dreyfus & Rabinow, 1982, pp.
   231-232). It is this "active relativism," this skeptical politics of
   knowledge, which more than anything else defines the continuing
   enchantment and intrigue of Foucault's work.
   
                                   NOTES
                                      
   1. Anthony Giddens has introduced this slogan in order to combat
   another dilemmatic antinomy: that which separates action theory from
   structural theory (e.g., Giddens, 1984, pp. xx-xxi). His idea of the
   "duality of structure" sensitizes to the simultaneously enabling and
   constraining effects of social institutions. My formulations also
   acknowledge the influence of Latour (1990, 1993), who has suggested
   the term "irreductionism" (Latour, 1984, p. 177ff).
   
   2. Duality and coincidence are hence not equivalent with identity or
   osmosis. Keenan speaks about the "difficult dash" that simultaneously
   joins and separates knowledge and power; "the dash is not a sign of
   equivalence, nor does it mark a covert dissimulation" (Keenan, 1987,
   pp. 12-13). Foucault has remarked that "when I read the thesis . . .
   'Knowledge is power' or 'Power is knowledge,' I begin to laugh, since
   studying their relation is precisely my problem" (1983, in Kelly,
   1994, pp. 132-133). That there is tension (residual?) and room (how
   much?) between the two concepts is also suggested by the following
   programmatic question: "How can the growth of capabilities be
   disconnected from the intensification of power relations?" (Foucault,
   1984b, p. 48). Cf. Barnes's view that knowledge and power are "one and
   the same thing" (1988, p. 169).
   
   3. While the vocabulary of ideology displays a nostalgia for a
   transparent, uncontaminated form of knowledge, the vocabulary of
   repression bespeaks of a similar nostalgia for a form of power
   "innocent of all coercion, discipline, and normalization" (Foucault,
   1980, p. 117).
   
   4. Cf. Connolly (1993, p. 366): "To reach 'beyond' the politics of
   good and evil is not to liquidate ethics but to become ashamed of the
   transcendentalization of conventional morality."
   
   5. This is an example offered by Foucault himself (Connoly, 1993, p.
   367).
   
   6. Connolly (1993) has precisely located the Foucaldian challenge to
   conventional morality as residing in this destabilization of the fixed
   transcendental dualism of good and evil, in pursuit of a higher, more
   generous ethical sensibility that does no longer constitute difference
   as evil, but is able to embrace it in relations of "agonistic
   respect." Cf. more extensively, Connly (1991).
   
   7. Cf. also Foucault's insistence that uncovering the conditions of
   acceptability of a discursive system cannot be separated from
   recognizing what made it difficult to accept it, "its arbitrariness in
   terms of knowledge, its violence in terms of power, in short, its
   energy" (1990/1994, p. 76).
   
   8. Fraser finds Foucault's work normatively confused because he
   "misunderstands . . . the way that norms function in social
   description . . . (and) fails to appreciate the degree to which the
   normative is embedded in and infused throughout the whole of language
   at every level" (Fraser, 1989, pp. 30-31). But such a normative
   embeddedness is quite compatible with the methodological import of
   Foucaldian genealogy as I read it here. I agree with Dreyfus and
   Rabinow's contention (1986, p. 115) that Foucault "does not propound a
   normative theory but that his work certainly has a normative thrust."
   Indeed, Foucault facilitates a more radical version of the value-fact
   proximity than Fraser considers possible.
   
   9. Connolly (1993, pp. 369, 373) employs terms such as "transcendental
   egoism" and "transcendental narcissism" in order to critically
   identify the "certification" of contingent identifies by their
   transformation into naturalized or ontological necessities. Put more
   simply: Critics such as Habermas fall prey to the (universal?)
   temptation to universalize their own rationalized personal experience,
   in order to escape its essential contingency. This, perhaps, is what
   moralizing is all about: It normatively magnifies and "necessitates"
   one's own life situation and its sociological and psychological
   limitations, while simultaneously erasing this generative experience
   from one's moral conscience. Moralizing hence implies both a
   self-effacement and a self-magnification; both an escape from self and
   a tendency to think that all others are essentially similar to oneself
   (which spreads the moral costs of a difficult identity).
   
   10. These renderings better capture what Foucault means by
   "desinvolture appliquee" and "desinvolture staidest" than the present
   English translation "studied casualness" (Foucault, 1972, p. 234).
   They are also closer to the "relentless erudition" demanded of
   genealogists in (Foucault, 1977b, p. 140).
   
   11. "History protects us from historicism from a historicism that
   calls on the past to resolve the questions of the present" (Foucault,
   1984a, p. 250).
   
   12. Dreyfus and Rabinow (1982) likewise underscore the "unequivocal
   and unabashed contemporary orientation" of the genealogical method,
   which at all times starts out with a diagnosis of the current
   situation (pp. 119, 232, 253).
   
   13. Cf. Dews (1987, p. 180ff) for a parallel critique. Cohen and Arato
   (1992) likewise identify a vicious circle: "Either the norms and
   projects articulated by social movements are strategies of
   counterpower and as such have no greater normative claim than those of
   other power seekers, or they simply reproduce the existing discourses
   of power. For a critical theory with a partisan intent, as Foucault's
   surely is, this is indeed a serious flaw" (pp. 295-296).
   
   14. Cf. also Dews (1987, pp. 189-191) who opines that Foucault's
   relativism is in tension with his political involvement, which
   continually forces him to sever the intimate connection between
   knowledge and power in order to be able to separate the illusory
   knowledge that is allied to power from the authentic knowledge that is
   allied to "resistance." In my interpretation such a break does not
   exist. "Resistance thinking" does not cease to be authentic, even if
   it in turn displays a (different, not less intimate) conjugation of
   knowledge and power. Cf. Hiley (1988, p. 86ff) for a similar view.
   
   15. "The problem is not of trying to dissolve [relations of power] in
   the utopia of a perfectly transparent communication, but to give
   oneself the rules of law, the techniques of management, and also the
   ethics, the ethos, the practices of the self, which would allow these
   games of power to be played with a minimum of domination" (Foucault,
   1988b, p. 18).
   
   16. On the proximity of the discourses of domination and liberation,
   see also Foucault (1972; 1978; 1984a, 10p. 96, 156-157).
   
   17. "Bad" knowledge fears and conjures away its own circularity;
   "good" knowledge acknowledges and celebrates it.
   
   18. In this sense, Foucault rejects all immanent critique, while
   Habermas's accusatory identification of "performative contradictions"
   typically presupposes its legitimacy. The idea of a performative
   contradiction projects an exogenous standard of evaluation into the
   adversary's work, which is subsequently exposed as riven by
   self-contradiction. Through such fifth column infiltration, the
   cognitive strength of the adversary is sapped from the inside. What
   appears as an indigenous flaw is in fact insinuated from the outside.
   The ventriloquist critic exonerates and absents himself from his
   projection, in that the contradiction is not between himself and his
   opponent, but between the opponent's own sayings and his actual
   doings. In this fashion, performative contradictions are essentially
   circular, but by their very grammar manage to conceal this
   circularity.
   
   19. Universalist claims, in my reading, are exaggerated attempts to
   carry local claims a little further, to enlarge their field of
   acceptance, to hold a broader audience. They are a power argument in
   intellectual negotiations. Universalists systematically overstate
   their case, because rights of maximum diffusion are claimed against
   all the world. Universalism performatively anticipates what can only
   be realized incrementally, contingently, practically, imperfectly.
   
   20. What Foucault aims at is to write the history of the
   "objectivation of objectivities" (Foucault, 1991b, p. 86).
   
   21. By itself, the idea of a productive argumentative circle offers an
   intriguing example of the proximity and interlacing of good and evil,
   which I take to be a distinctive feature of a skeptical ethic of
   knowledge politics.
   
                                 REFERENCES
                                      
   Armstrong, T. J., (Ed.). (1992). Michel Foucault: Philosopher. New
   York: Routledge.
   
   Barnes, B. (1988). The nature of power. Cambridge: Polity Press.
   
   Bernstein, R. (1994). Foucault: Critique as a philosophic ethos. In M.
   Kelly (Ed.), Critique and power. Recasting the Foucault,/Habermas
   debate (pp. 211-241). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
   
   Bourdieu, P. (1989). The corporatism of the universal. The role of
   intellectuals in the modem world. Telos, 81, 99-110.
   
   Bourdieu, P. (1991). Les regles de l'art. Paris: Seuil.
   
   Callon, M., Law, J., & Rip, A. (FzzAs.). (1986). Mapping the dynamics
   of science. London: MacMillan.
   
   Cohen, J. L., & Arato, A. (1992). Civil society and political theory.
   Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
   
   Connolly, W. E. (1985). Taylor, Foucault, and otherness. Political
   Theory, 13(3), 365-376.
   
   Connolly, W. E. (1991). Identity/Difference. Democratic negotiations
   of political paradox. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
   
   Connolly, W. E. (1993). Beyond good and evil. The ethical sensibility
   of Michel Foucault. Political Theory, 21(3), 365-389.
   
   Dews, P. (1987). Logics of disintegration. London: Verso.
   
   Dreyfus, H., & Rabinow, P. (1982). Michel Foucault. Beyond
   structuralism and hermeneutics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
   
   Dreyfus, H., & Rabinow, P. (1986). What is maturity? Habermas and
   Foucault on "What is Enlightenment?". In D.C. Hoy (Ed.),
   
   Foucault: A critical reader. Oxford: Blackwell. Foucault, M. (1965).
   Madness and civilization. New York: Pantheon.
   
   Foucault, M. (1972). The Archaeology of Knowledge. New York: Harper
   Torchbooks.
   
   Foucault, M. (1977a). Discipline and punish. Harmondsworth: Penguin
   Books.
   
   Foucault, M. (1977b). Nietzsche, genealogy, history. In D. F. Bouthard
   (Ed.), Language, counter-memory, practice. Oxford: Blackwell.
   
   Foucault, M. (1978). The history of sexuality I: An introduction. New
   York: Random House.
   
   Foucault, M. (1980). Power/Knowledge: Selected interviews and other
   writings 1972-1977 (C. Gordon, Ed.). New York: Pantheon.
   
   Foucault, M. (1982). The subject and power. In H. Dreyfus & P. Rabinow
   (Eds.), Michel Foucault. Beyond structuralism and hermeneutics.
   Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
   
   Foucault, M. (1983). Structuralism and post-structuralism. Telos, 55.
   
   Foucault, M. (1984a). Space, knowledge, and power. In P. Rabinow
   (Ed.), The Foucault reader. New York: Pantheon.
   
   Foucault, M. (1984b). What is enlightenment? In P. Rabinow (Ed.), The
   Foucault reader. New York: Pantheon.
   
   Foucault, M. (1988a). Politics, philosophy, culture. Interviews and
   other writings 1977-1984 (L. D. Kritzman, Ed.). New York: Routledge.
   
   Foucault, M. (1988b). Truth, power, self. In L. Martin, H. Gutman, &
   P. Hutton (Eds.), Technologies of the self. Amherst: University of
   Massachusetts Press.
   
   Foucault, M. (1991a). Politics and the study of discourse. In G.
   Burcheil, C. Gordon, & P. Miller (Eds.), The Foucault effect. Studies
   in governmentality. London: Harvester.
   
   Foucault, M. (1991b). Questions of method. In G. Burcheil, C. Gordon,
   & P. Miller (Eds.), The Foucault effect. Studies in governmentality.
   London: Harvester.
   
   Foucault, M. (1994). Kritiek en Verlichting (Dutch Translation of
   Qu'est-ce que la critique? [Critique et Auflklarung]) [What is
   Critique? Critique and enlightenment]. Krisis. Tijdschrift voor
   filosofie, 56 (September). (Original work published 1990)
   
   Fraser, N. (1989). Unruly practices. Cambridge: Polity.
   
   Giddens, A. (1984). The constitution of society. Cambridge: Polity.
   
   Gouldner, A. W. (1973). For sociology. London: Allen Lane.
   
   Habermas, J. (1987). The philosophical discourse of modernity.
   Cambridge: Polity.
   
   Habermas, J. (1992). Faktizitat und Geltung [Facticity and validity].
   Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
   
   Hiley, D. R. (1988). Philosophy in question. Essays on a Pyrrhonian
   theme. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
   
   Honneth, A. (1994). Foucault's theory of society: A systems-theoretic
   dissolution of the Dialectic of Enlightenment. In M. Kelly (Ed.),
   Critique and power Recasting the Foucault/Habermas debate (pp.
   243-282). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
   
   Keenan, T. (1987). The "paradox" of knowledge and power: Reading
   Foucault on a bias. Political Theory, 15(1), 5-37.
   
   Kelly, M. (1994). Foucault, Habermas, and the self-referentiality of
   critique. In M. Kelly (Ed.), Critique and power Recasting the
   Foucault/Habermas debate (pp. 365-400). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
   
   Kunneman, H. (1986). De waarheidstrechter. Meppel: Boom.
   
   Lacroix, B. (1981). Durkheim et le politique. Paris: Presses de la
   Fondation Nationale des sciences politiques.
   
   Latour, B. (1983). Give me a laboratory and I will raise the world. In
   K. Knorr & M. Mulkay (Eds.), Science observed. London: Sage.
   
   Latour, B. (1984). Les microbes. Guerre etpaix. Paris: Fayard.
   
   Latour, B. (1986). The powers of association. In J. Law (Ed.), Power,
   action, and belief. A new sociology of knowledge ?. London: Routledge.
   
   Latour, B. (1987). Science in action. Milton Keynes: Open University
   Press.
   
   Latour, B. (1990). Postmodem? No, simply amodem! Steps towards an
   anthropology of science. Studies in the History and Philosophy of
   Science, 21,165-171.
   
   Latour, B. (1991). The impact of science studies on political
   philosophy. Science, Technology, and Human Values, 16(1), 3-19.
   
   Latour, B. (1993). We have never been modern. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
   University Press.
   
   Law, J. (1986). Power, action, and belief. A new sociology of
   knowledge?. London: Routledge.
   
   Lukes, S. (1982). Introduction. In Durkheim (Ed.), The Rules of
   Scientific Method. London: MacMillan.
   
   McCarthy, T. (1994). The critique of impure reason: Foucault and the
   Frankfurt School. In M. Kelly (Ed.), Critique and power. Recasting the
   Foucault, Habermas debate (pp. 243-282). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
   
   Pels, D. (1983). Het project als object. Durkheim's kennispolifiek in
   relafivistisch perspectief [The project as object. Durkheim and the
   politics of theory]. Amsterdams Sociologisch Tijdschrift, 10(1),
   51-91.
   
   Pels, D. (1987). Macht of eigendom? Een kwestie van intellectuele
   rivalitelt. Amsterdam: Van Gennep.
   
   Pels, D. (1990). De natuurlijke saamhorigheid van feiten en waarden.
   [The natural proximity of facts and values]. Kennis & Methode, 14(1),
   14-43.
   
   Pels, D. (1993). Het democratisch verschil. Jacques de Kadt en de
   nieuwe elite. Amsterdam: Van Gennep.
   
   Pels, D. (1995). Knowledge politics and anti-politics? Toward a
   critical appraisal of Bourdieu's concept of intellectual autonomy.
   Theory and Society, 24, 79-104.
   
   Pels, D. (in press). Property or power? A study in intellectual
   rivalry. New York: Guilford.
   
   Rabinow, P. (Ed.). (1984). The Foucault reader. New York: Pantheon.
   
   Rajchman, J. (1985). Foucault. The freedom of philosophy. New York:
   Columbia University Press.
   
   Rochlitz, R. (I 992). The aesthetics of existence: Post-conventional
   morality and the theory of power in Michel Foucault. In T J. Armstrong
   (Ed.), Michel Foucault: Philosopher. New York: Routledge.
   
   Root, M. (1993). Philosophy of social science. Oxford: Blackwell.
   
   Rouse, J. (1987). Knowledge and power. Ithaca: Cornell University
   Press.
   
   Shapin, S. (1994). A social history of truth. Gentility, credibility,
   and scientific knowledge in seventeenth-century England. Chicago:
   University of Chicago Press.
   
   Taylor, C. (1985). Connolly, Foucault, and truth. Political Theory,
   13(3), 377-385.
   
   Taylor, C. (1986). Foucault on freedom and truth. In D.C. Hoy (Ed.),
   Foucault: A critical reader. Oxford: Blackwell.
   
   Visker, R. (1990). Genealogie als kritiek. Michel Foucault en de
   menswetenschappen. Meppel: Boom.
   
   ~~~~~~~~
   
   By DICK PELS
   
   University of Amsterdam
                             _________________
   
   Copyright of American Behavioral Scientist is the property of Sage
   Publications Inc. and its content may not be copied or emailed to
   multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's
   express written permission. However, users may print, download, or
   email articles for individual use.
   Source: American Behavioral Scientist, Jun/Jul95, Vol. 38 Issue 7,
   p1018, 24p.
   Item Number: 9508010123
   
   

Link to Foucault Page
Kindly click here to return to Foucault Page

Kindly click here to return to Academic Interests
Please click here to return to Additional Information

page last updated 28 October 2004
Copyright © 2004 Miguel B. Llora, MA. All Rights Reserved.
Best viewed on Internet Explorer 5.x or later at a minimum of 1024 x 768 resolution